Yi Ik on Compassion and Grief
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Mencius’ Ambivalence
Here is why I say all human beings have a mind that commiserates with others. Now, if anyone were suddenly to see a child about to fall into a well, his mind would be filled with alarm, distress, compassion, and commiseration. That he would react accordingly is not because he would hope to use the opportunity to ingratiate himself with the child’s parents, nor because he would seek commendation from neighbors and friends, nor because he would hate the adverse reputation [that could come from not reacting accordingly]. From this it may be seen that one who lacks a mind that feels compassion and commiseration would not be human. … The mind’s feeling of compassion and commiseration is the sprout of benevolence.(Mencius 2A6)
Nowadays, if a mother who is carrying her child on her back drops the child into the well while drawing water, she will certainly follow and drag it out. Nowadays, if there is a disastrous year with famine among the people and they are starving by the roadside, this is much greater source of distress than dropping a child. How can one not examine this?(Mozi, “The Seven Kinds of Anxiety”)11
3. Yi Ik’s View on the Four Beginnings and Seven Feelings
Pleasure (hui 喜) is like we take pleasure in [certain] sounds and colors. Anger (no 怒) is like we are angry at something that goes against [our minds]. Grief (ae 哀) is like we grieve over death and loss. Fear (gu 懼) is like we are afraid of hierarchical power and military force. Love (ae 愛) is like we are fond of something likable [to our minds]. Dislike (o 惡) is like we dislike bad odor. Desire (yok 欲) is like we desire clothes and food.(“2. Meaning of the Seven Feelings”)22
In my opinion, cheuk 惻 (compassion) is [a feeling of] sadness and pain, just as one feels sad and pain when one is stabbed. Eun 隱 (commiseration) is that sadness and pain shake each other subtly, just as a shout subtly echoes through a valley and knocking on a thing subtly affects the qi within it.(“1. Meaning of the Four Beginnings”)24
Commiseration among the Four Beginnings is different from grief among the Seven Feelings. Commiseration is to commiserate with other things. This is gong 公. Grief is to feel grief for [things related to] oneself. This is sa 私. … When one sees something about to die, one commiserates with it, but this is not grief. When one is in trouble, hardship, sickness, or pain, one feels grief, but this is not commiseration. This is the distinction between commiseration and grief.(“1. Meaning of the Four Beginnings”)
The mind of compassion and commiseration … are [morally] good affairs. As for grief…, the worthy and unworthy alike have them. Therefore, the Great Learning (Daxue大學) says, “People are partial in regard to what they feel grief over and pity for; they are partial in regard to what they consider lowly and detestable.” People are surely partial in regard to what they feel grief over and pity for and what they consider lowly and detestable. However, it is rare that people are partial in regard to what they feel compassion for and commiserate with.(“1. Meaning of the Four Beginnings”)
The sages and the stupid all have the desire for food and sex and the dislike of death, loss, poverty, and hardship. [However,] when the desire stops at what is proper to desire and the dislike stops at what is proper to dislike, they are the correctness within sa (私中之正). What does it mean to be correct? Even though one’s feelings are not separated from [what is related to] oneself, they do not go astray.(“4. The Seven Feelings of Sages and Worthies”)
In general, the Seven Feelings are what one is capable of [experiencing] without learning… [On the contrary,] the Four Beginnings are not what one is capable of [experiencing] without learning. What does this mean? Suppose there is a person who does not learn. In the beginning, he cannot but also have the Dao Mind; however, if this mind is repeatedly fettered, he will lose this mind completely.32 Therefore, some people are incorrigibly unfeeling and do not show the Four Beginnings at all.33 [On the contrary,] there is no one who does not possess [the Seven Feelings] such as pleasure and anger. The Seven Feelings do not have anything to do with learning. They are not separated from oneself, and that’s all.(“4. The Seven Feelings of Sages and Worthies”)
4. Yi Ik’s Conception of the Sage
If one desires together what people in the world desire and one dislikes together what people in the world dislike, this is the gong within sa (私中之公). How come is this gong? Even though [people in the world] are not related to oneself, one regards them in the same way one regards oneself.(“4. The Seven Feelings of Sages and Worthies”)
When ill and sick, people are fearful. When hungry and cold, they are sad. These are the root of the Seven Feelings and they do not have anything to do with the Four Beginnings. [However,] when my child is ill and sick, I am also fearful. When my child is hungry and cold, I am also sad. This is not necessarily so for the child of another person. This is because father and son share the same body and there is no gap between me and him. Therefore, when my son is sad and fearful, I am also sad and fearful. [However,] in the case of the son of another person, these [feelings] ought to become slow and mild, because there is a gap between me and a son of another person. My sadness and fear do not yet extend [to him].(“11. The Seven Feelings are also issued from the Dao Mind”)
In the world, some people are incorrigibly unfeeling. Even though their own sons are ill, sick, hungry, and cold, they are not sad and fearful for them. However, when such people are themselves ill, sick, hungry, and cold, there has never been a time when they are not sad and fearful for themselves. As for these people, the beginnings of compassion and commiseration are blocked and do not penetrate, not reaching even to their own child.(“11. The Seven Feelings are also issued from the Dao Mind”)
When one sees a child about to fall into a well, the principle of benevolence immediately responds without relying on the qi of one’s physical form. As soon as there is this response, it immediately touches and stimulates the qi of one’s physical form, and the feelings of grief and fear come forth and arise.(“11. The Seven Feelings are also issued from the Dao Mind”)
If a son of another person is so ill, sick, hungry, and cold that he is about to die, I also feel grief and fear for him. [This is because] upon encountering the most urgent and intense cases, the mind of compassion and commiseration is suddenly manifested.(“11. The Seven Feelings are also issued from the Dao Mind”)
In the case of a child crawling into a well, life and death is decided in a moment. Therefore, one certainly feels alarm, distress, and fear, and one feels compassion, commiseration, and grief. When facing a moment of the most urgent and intense situation, in that moment the thought of [what is related to] oneself has not yet occurred [in one’s mind], … Like a river bursting its banks or a torrent of rain pouring down, there is no time to distinguish me and another person so that the pain feels as if it is mine.(“11. The Seven Feelings are also issued from the Dao Mind”)
5. Conclusions
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Mencius 2A6. The concern for the well-being includes animals as well. See Mencius in 1A7. |
2 | Youngmin Kim introduces Wang Tingxiang’s thought experiment and his political ideas in his A History of Chinese Political Thought (Y. Kim 2018, pp. 167–73). According to Wang Tingxiang, the reason we do not blame the person who save his/her own child first is not because our familial affection is natural for us, but because the sages set up the moral standard in such a way. This shows that even though Confucians would give the same answer to this moral conflict, their reasoning can be different. Therefore, it is incredibly important to clarify why each thinker offers the answer as they may do. |
3 | His pen name is Seongho 星湖 (Starry Lake). For a brief introduction of his thought, see (Youn 2015, pp. 591–611). |
4 | Mencius also likens our moral inclinations to four limbs. Human babies are born with four limbs, but they cannot use their limbs properly. However, as they grow older, they can walk and run. At full capacity, they can use their limbs as swiftly as Serena Williams. For a general introduction of the Mencian cultivation program, see (Ivanhoe 2000, pp. 15–28). |
5 | Mencius discusses the second sprout, the feeling of shame and disdain, in 6A10. I use “compassion” for both characters 惻隱 (cheuk-eun), unless it is necessary not to. |
6 | Mencius 4B19. One way to understand Mencius’ distinction between human beings and non-human animals is our ability to develop moral inclinations into virtues. |
7 | In his evolutionary account of Mencius’ thought, Kanghun Ahn points out that even though mammals do show a high level of compassion, their compassion is mostly directed to their babies, kin, or their friends (Ahn 2022, p. 368). The morality of non-human animals became an important issue for later Confucians. See (Back 2018). |
8 | Ivanhoe points out that Mencius’ thought experiment has both theoretical and therapeutic aims (Ivanhoe 2016, p. 3). |
9 | 孺子 yuja in Mencius’ passage means an infant at the breast, thus referring to a very young child, such as a toddler. |
10 | Hagop Sarkissian made a connection between this study and Mencius’ thought experiment in his talk, “Evolution, Moral Nativism, and Mencius’s Four Sprouts,” on 7 November 2017 at Sungkyunkwan University. |
11 | Thanks to Jeong-geun Shin for drawing my attention to this passage. |
12 | Another difference is that in Mozi’s case, it is the fault of the mother who dropped the child, but in Mencius’ case, it is nobody’s fault. |
13 | According to Bryan Van Norden, in the Mozi, we find the first use of thought experiments in Chinese history or perhaps throughout history. We also find a case comparable to Thomas Hobbes’ state of nature argument in the Mozi (Van Norden 2007, pp. 162–66, 79). |
14 | If a child about to fall into a well (2A6) is a case that explains the feeling of compassion, the account of the origin of funerary practice in Mencius 3A5 can be considered as a case that explains natural affection for our parents. |
15 | In his study of moral extension in the Mencius, Doil Kim identifies four different types of extension. The first two are the extension of compassion for others in general and the extension of familial affection. The other two are the diffusion model and the expansion of mind model. The last one is found in Zhu Xi’s interpretation of Mencius (D. Kim 2018). |
16 | Hagop Sarkissian writes an interesting article to dispute Liu’s claim with empirical research (Sarkissian 2020). In addition, by analyzing the discontinuity between the familial and the political domains in the Mencius, Tao Jiang presents a nuanced and complex picture of the Mencian program, dividing it into two stands: the extensionist and the sacrificialist. His point is that for Mencius, the familial virtue is not only a medium for the political virtues, but it is featured as an end in itself. In this respect, his position is, on the whole, in line with Qingping Liu (Tao 2020). |
17 | Similar to Chan, Myeong-seok Kim interprets both universal compassion and filial affection as concern-based construal, belonging to the feeling of compassion (惻隱). He provides an interesting comparison between the case of a baby about to fall into a well (2A6, compassion) and the case of the origin of funerary practice (3A5, filial affection) (M.-s. Kim 2010). It is interesting to note that according to Kanghun Ahn’s evolutionary account, other-regarding proclivities (universal compassion) are the default setting, and group-orientedness comes later through cultural molding (Ahn 2022). |
18 | According to Hagop Sarkissian, scholars in this group include David Wong and Stephen Angle (Sarkissian 2010, pp. 732–33). |
19 | The New Compilation of the Four–Seven Debate is a collection containing a preface, 16 essays, 2 diagrams, and 6 additional essays in the appendices. The titles of the 16 essays and 2 diagrams are: “1. Meaning of the Four Beginnings”; “2. Meaning of the Seven Feelings”; “3. Cases in which the Four Beginnings are not Perfectly Measured”; “4. The Seven Feelings of Sages and Worthies”; “5. Similarities between the Four Beginnings and Seven Feelings”; “6. The Seven Feelings pass through the Four Beginnings horizontally”; “7. Difference between the Four Beginnings and Seven Feelings”; “8. The Seven Feelings are simply the Human Mind”; “9. The Seven Feelings follow the commands of the Four Beginnings”; “10. The Seven Feelings also do not have anything that is not good”; “11. The Seven Feelings are also issued from the Dao Mind”; “12. Ancient people’s Discussions on Feelings are Different”; “13. Analogy of Riding on Boat”; “14. Analogy of the Moon on the River”; “15. Elaboration of the Theory of Riding on a Horse”; “16. Explanation of the Diagrams”; “Diagram of the Human Mind and Dao Mind”; and “Diagram of the Four Beginnings and Seven Feelings.” The primary text of his New Compilation of the Four–Seven Debate is found in the database of the standardized edition of the Complete Works of Seongho (星湖全書). http://waks.aks.ac.kr/rsh/?rshID=AKS-2011-EBZ-2103 (accessed on 9 February 2023). |
20 | I think the Four Sprouts is the most appropriate translation of sadan 四端 in the Mencius. However, according to neo-Confucian metaphysics, sadan refers to a clue or an indication of the perfect moral nature in human beings. In other words, for Mencius, sadan is the beginning point of cultivation, whereas for neo-Confucians, sadan is similar to a branch tip of a tree through which we can know the existence of the root underneath—which is to say our original nature. Because most Korean Confucians during the Joseon dynasty followed the Cheng-Zhu neo-Confucianism, I translate sadan as the Four Beginnings in a more neutral tone. For a detailed explanation of Zhu Xi’s interpretation of sadan, see (Ivanhoe 2000, p. 46). |
21 | There are other sets of everyday emotions often mentioned in the Four–Seven Debate: the four feelings of pleasure, anger, sorrow, and joy in the Doctrine of the Mean (Zhongyong中庸); the six feelings of sorrow, joy, pleasure, anger, reverence, and love in the “Record of Music” (Yueji 樂記) of the Records of Ritual; and the seven feelings of pleasure, anger, sorrow, joy, love, dislike, and desire in Cheng Yi’s 程頤 (1033–1107) “Discourse on What Master Yan Loved to Learn (Yanzi suo hao he xue lun顏子所好何學論).“ |
22 | Yi Ik’s writings in this paper are from his New Compilation of the Four–Seven Debate. The translations of his writings are mine. |
23 | Michael Kalton translated the two major debates of Yi Hwang—Gi Daeseung 奇大升 (1527–1572) and Seong Hon 成渾 (1535–1598)—Yi I (Kalton 1994). For a summary of this debate, you can refer to (Ivanhoe 2015; 2016, pp. 78–89). |
24 | Paul Ekman’s study is very helpful for understanding Yi Ik’s description of human feelings. According to Ekman, the death of one’s child is a universal cause for sadness and agony. In addition, people go through the repeating process between protesting agony and resigned sadness (Ekman 2003, pp. 82–109). The states of cheuk 惻 (compassion) and eun 隱 (commiseration) may be similar to the ongoing process between agony and sadness. |
25 | “5. Similarities between the Four Beginnings and Seven Feelings.” According to these descriptions, the difference between felt compassion and felt grief, if any, appears to be the intensity of feelings. This will be discussed later. |
26 | This is also the criterion for distinguishing the Four Beginnings from the Seven Feelings. In “7. Differences between the Four Beginnings and Seven Feelings,” Yi Ik advises, “The difference between gong and sa is like the gap between heaven and an abyss. They are markedly different so that those without wisdom can also understand it.” |
27 | Yi Ik also mentions this point in “7. Difference between the Four Beginnings and Seven Feelings.” |
28 | We usually feel grief for the misfortune of our own child, but it is possible that certain people feel compassion for the misfortune of their own child. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for alerting me to this point. In addition, Yi Ik identifies that certain people would not be affected even by the suffering of their own child. This case will be discussed later. |
29 | In my view, the impartial aspect of the Four Beginnings is best explained by what Winnie Sung calls “unmediated perspective,” the perspective from which things appear to me that is not mediated by another perspective, such as the victim’s perspective or the point of view of the universe. She points out that the unmediated perspective does not contrast either with the first-, second-, or third-person perspective. Instead, we simply react consciously and immediately when “The child is about to fall into a well” (Sung 2019, pp. 1105–6). Because this is not mediated by any other perspectives, we can call this reaction impartial. |
30 | Accordingly, this kind of impartial feeling of compassion is immune to the criticism of scholars, such as Jesse Prinz, who are wary of the role of empathy or compassion for its biases toward people who are in a special relationship. Jing Hu challenges this type of contemporary critique of empathy by engaging with Mencius’ model in regard to the extension of compassion to the suffering of outer-group members (Prinz 2011; Hu 2018). In Yi Ik’s view, if compassion is biased toward people who are in a special relation, it cannot be called compassion, but it should be called grief. As I will argue, Yi Ik’s interest lies in how to transform unmotivating compassion into motivating grief. |
31 | As you see in the quotation, the actual wording of Yi Ik is the correctness within sa (私中之正). Because sa is difficult to translate into English and also in this context, sa refers to the Seven Feelings, I call it “the correctness of the Seven Feelings.” In addition, we can consider morally bad cases of the Seven Feelings as the wrongness within sa (私中之邪), even though Yi Ik does not use this term. For the same reason, I call this case “the wrongness of the Seven Feelings.” |
32 | Here, the Dao Mind refers to the mode of mind in which the Heavenly Principle (the original human nature) is in operation. In this paper, one can consider the Dao Mind simply as the Four Beginnings. Yi Ik also makes this point clear in “8. The Seven Feelings are simply the Human Mind.” |
33 | “Unfeeling” is a translation of bulin 不仁, the literal translation of which is “not benevolent.” For a discussion of this translation, see (Ivanhoe 2017, pp. 47–48). |
34 | As noted earlier, according to Wang Tingxiang, what makes this action morally right is the sages, not our natural affection. |
35 | In “11. The Seven Feelings are also issued from the Dao Mind,” Yi Ik also makes this point. The case of the child at the well is the most urgent and intense case through which Mencius tried to show people the manifestation of the Four Beginnings. |
36 | Joshua Greene provides an evolutionary account of our different responses to the child on the opposite side of the earth (impersonal moral dilemma) and the drowning child in front of us (personal moral dilemma) (Greene 2003). Furthermore, in her study of Mencius, Winnie Sung makes a conceptual distinction between a psychological state in which one sees one’s agency as having a bearing on others’ being harmed (不忍人之心) and a psychological state in which one does not hold such a view. In order to explain this difference, she provides a following example: “Lisa is watching the news about refugees on TV and finds it difficult to bear the suffering of the refugees. However, she does not see herself as either the one who inflicts harm on these refugees or someone who is in a position where she could have prevented the suffering of the refugees.” According to Sung, this case can be considered as compassion, but cannot be considered as the mind that cannot bear to harm others because Lisa does not see that her action could in anyway make a difference (Sung 2019, pp. 1102–4). If we follow her explanation, our different responses to the child on the opposite side of the earth and the drowning child in front of us are due to different perceptions of our agency in relation to the suffering of others. |
37 | Many scholars have presented their own interpretations of the Mencian program of cultivation. I will return to this point in the conclusion. |
38 | Based on Yi Ik’s three different levels of gong and sa, Seonhee Kim divides Yi Ik’s social reformism into three parts (S. Kim 2013). |
39 | According to Seonhee Kim, in order for one’s desire not to cause harm to others, Yi Ik emphasizes frugality. This is because even when one accumulates wealth even in a proper way, this can cause others who lack such wealth to feel jealousy and have the desire to steal (S. Kim 2013, pp. 351–54). |
40 | “4. The Seven Feelings of Sages and Worthies”. |
41 | In “4. the Seven Feelings of Sages and Worthies,” he also writes that “The sa of common people reaches near, whereas the sa of sages reach afar.” |
42 | “4. The Seven Feelings of Sages and Worthies.” |
43 | When I argue that sages form one body with all the people or embrace the whole world, this does not refer to the inclusiveness or extensiveness of the sages’ concern in abstract form. Rather, I mean that in each particular interaction with others, sages form one body with them and include them in the scope of their partial concern. |
44 | “4. The Seven Feelings of Sages and Worthies.” The original text is written as 聖人偏愛人類 in all the five versions of the manuscript of the New Compilation of the Four–Seven Debate (the Central Library version of Gyeongsang National University, the Asami Collection version of Berkeley University, the Central Library version of Chungnam National University, and the two versions of the National Library of Korea). Lee Sangik, who translates this work into Korean, notes that the character 偏 (pyeon) is probably a typo of either 徧 (pyeon/byeon) or 遍 (byeon), which renders the sentence to mean: “Sages love humanity inclusively or universally” (Lee 1999, p. 37). We do not find another case of 偏愛 or any other case of 徧愛or遍愛 in the entire collection of Yi Ik’s writings. If we take the character as a typo, the meaning accords with the overall view of Yi Ik. If we follow the original character, the meaning not only accords with the view of Yi Ik, but also highlights the unique contribution of Yi Ik’s thought, even if he did not mean to use that character itself. |
45 | Stephen Dawall understands Mencian compassion as a sympathetic concern or sympathy, thus distinguishing it from empathy. Unlike empathy, which needs not involve concern, sympathy is felt as if from the perspective of the one caring (Darwall 1998, p. 261). |
46 | The other paradigmatic case is found in Shun’s anger against the betrayal of the four villains. |
47 | According to Mencius’s appraisal, Yuezhengzi is a person who loves the good. |
48 | Based on certain views of East Asian thinkers, Philip Ivanhoe presents the oneness hypothesis and its implications with respect to the theories of virtue and human flourishing in contemporary societies. According to him, the oneness hypothesis is the idea that human beings are “intricately and inextricably intertwined with the other people, creatures, and things in ways that dispose us to care for the rest of world as much as we care for ourselves.” (Ivanhoe 2017, p. 30). In regard to this, I believe Yi Ik’s view falls within the family views of the oneness hypothesis, thereby offering us an interesting and distinctive version. |
49 | Even though the term developmental model of self-cultivation is first used by A. C. Graham (Graham 1989), it is Philip Ivanhoe who draws on this term and extends it to other Confucian thinkers, thereby defining their distinct systems of cultivation program with different titles. |
50 | The secondary literature on this issue is summarized well in Winnie Sung’s essay (Sung 2019, p. 1110). |
51 | In their recent research article, Jing Hu and Seth Robertson attempt to show how the Mencian program of moral cultivation can provide helpful insights with respect to the anti-realist accounts of moral progress. According to their view, an important contribution of the Mencian program is to shift and improve moral perspectives: that is, how we perceive, interpret, understand, and react to certain situations. An exemplary case that they provide is Mencius 1A7, in which Mencius helped King Xuan of Qi to see an ox being led to sacrifice as if an innocent prisoner was led to execution (Hu and Robertson 2021). I think this shift in perspective can apply to Yi Ik’s system: to see another person who is unrelated to oneself as if they are related to oneself. |
References
- Ahn, Kanghun. 2022. The Origin of Human Morality: An Evolutionary Perspective on Mencius’s Notion of Sympathy. Asian Philosophy 32: 365–82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Back, Youngsun. 2018. Are Animals Moral?: Zhu Xi and Jeong Yakyong’s Views on Nonhuman Animals. Asian Philosophy 28: 97–116. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chan, Alan. 2004a. Does xiao come before ren? In Filial Piety in Chinese Thought and History. Edited by Alan K. L. Chan and Sor-hoon Tan. London: Routledge, pp. 154–75. [Google Scholar]
- Chan, Sin Yee. 2004b. Filial piety, Commiseration, and the Virtue of Ren. In Filial Piety in Chinese Thought and History. Edited by Alan K. L. Chan and Sor-hoon Tan. London: Routledge, pp. 176–88. [Google Scholar]
- Darwall, Stephen. 1998. Sympathy, Empathy, Care. Philosophical Studies 89: 261–81. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ekman, Paul. 2003. Emotions Revealed: Recognizing Faces and Feelings to Improve Communication and Emotional Life. New York: Times Books. [Google Scholar]
- Glocker, Melanie L., Daniel D. Langleben, Kosha Ruparel, James W. Loughead, Ruben C. Gur, and Norbert Sachser. 2009. Baby Schema in Infant Faces Induces Cuteness Perception and Motivation for Caretaking in Adults. Ethology 115: 257–63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Graham, Angus Charles. 1989. Two Chinese Philosophers: The Metaphysics of the Brothers Cheng. La Salle: Open Court Press. [Google Scholar]
- Greene, Joshua. 2003. From neutral ‘is’ to moral ‘ought’: What are the moral implications of neuroscientific moral psychology? Nature Reviews Neuroscience 4: 847–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hu, Jing. 2018. Empathy for Non-Kin, the Faraway, the Unfamiliar, and the Abstract—An Interdisciplinary Study on Mencian Moral Cultivation and a Response to Prinz. Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 17: 349–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hu, Jing, and Seth Robertson. 2021. Constructing Morality with Mengzi: Three Lessons on the Metaethics of Moral Progress. In Comparative Metaethics: Neglected Perspectives on the Foundations of Morality. Edited by Colin Marshall. New York: Routledge, pp. 179–97. [Google Scholar]
- Ivanhoe, Philip J. 2000. Confucian Moral Self Cultivation. Indianapolis: Hackett. [Google Scholar]
- Ivanhoe, Philip J. 2002. Ethics in the Confucian Tradition: The Thought of Mengzi and Wang Yangming. Indianapolis: Hackett. [Google Scholar]
- Ivanhoe, Philip J. 2015. The Historical Significance and Contemporary Relevance of the Four-Seven Debate. Philosophy East & West 65: 401–29. [Google Scholar]
- Ivanhoe, Philip J. 2016. Three Streams: Confucian Reflections on Learning & the Moral Heart-Mind in China, Korea, and Japan. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ivanhoe, Philip J. 2017. Oneness: East Asian Conceptions of Virtue, Happiness, & How We are All Connected. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kalton, Michael. 1994. The Four-Seven Debate-An Annotated Translation of the Most Famous Controversy in Korean Neo-Confucian Thought. Albany: State University of New York. [Google Scholar]
- Kim, Doil. 2018. Four Types of Moral Extension in Mencius. Journal of Confucian Philosophy and Culture 29: 1–19. [Google Scholar]
- Kim, Myeong-seok. 2010. What Ceyin zhi xin (Compassion/Familial Affection) Really Is. Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 9: 407–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kim, Seonhee. 2013. Inyeomui gong (公) eseo silhaengui sa (私) ro: Gongsa gwanjeomeseo bon Seongho Yi Ikue sahoe gaehyeokron (From Theoretical gong to Practical sa: Seongho Yi Ik’s Social Reformism from the perspective of the concepts of gong an sa). Hanguk Sasangsahak 45: 339–71. [Google Scholar]
- Kim, Youngmin. 2018. A History of Chinese Political Thought. Cambridge: Polity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lee, Sangyik, trans. 1999. Sachil Sinpyeon Yeokju (Translation and Annotation of the New Compilation of the Four-Seven by Yi Ik). Seoul: Daunsaem. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, Qingping. 2003. Filiality versus Sociality and Individuality: On Confucianism as ‘Consanguinitism. Philosophy East & West 53: 234–50. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, Qingping. 2004. Is Mencius’ Doctrine of ‘Extending Affection’ Tenable? Asian Philosophy 14: 79–90. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Liu, Qingping. 2006. On Confucius’ Principle of Consanguineous Affection: A Reading of the Dialogue about the Three-Year Mourning in the Lunyu. Asian Philosophy 16: 173–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Liu, Qingping. 2007. Confucianism and Corruption: An Analysis of Shun’s Two Actions Described by Mencius. Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 6: 1–19. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, Qingping. 2009. To Become a Filial Son, a Loyal Subject, or a Humane Person?-On the Confucian Ideas about Humanity. Asian Philosophy 19: 173–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Prinz, Jesse. 2011. Against Empathy. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 49: 214–33. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sarkissian, Hagop. 2010. Recent Approaches to Confucian Filial Morality. Philosophy Compass 5: 725–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sarkissian, Hagop. 2020. Do Filial Values Corrupt? How Can We Know? Clarifying and Assessing the Recent Confucian Debate. Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 19: 193–207. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sung, Winnie. 2019. Bu Ren 不忍 (Cannot Bear to Harm) in the Mencius. Philosophy East & West 69: 1098–119. [Google Scholar]
- Sung, Winnie. 2021. Cultivating Goodness or Manifesting Goodness: Two Interpretations of the Mencius. In Skill in Ancient Ethics: The Legacy of China, Greece and Rome. Edited by Tom Angier and Lisa Raphals. London: Bloomsbury Academic, pp. 203–20. [Google Scholar]
- Tao, Jiang. 2020. Ambivalence of Family and Disunity of Virtues in Mencius’ Political Philosophy. Journal of Confucian Philosophy and Culture 33: 69–104. [Google Scholar]
- Van Norden, Bryan. 2007. Virtue Ethics and Consequentialism. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Youn, Sa-soon, ed. 2015. Korean Philosophy: Sources and Interpretations. Seoul: Korea University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Zhao, Wenqing. 2014. Is Contemporary Chinese Society Inhumane? What Mencius and Empirical Psychology Have to Say. Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 13: 343–60. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Back, Y. Yi Ik on Compassion and Grief. Religions 2023, 14, 255. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14020255
Back Y. Yi Ik on Compassion and Grief. Religions. 2023; 14(2):255. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14020255
Chicago/Turabian StyleBack, Youngsun. 2023. "Yi Ik on Compassion and Grief" Religions 14, no. 2: 255. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14020255
APA StyleBack, Y. (2023). Yi Ik on Compassion and Grief. Religions, 14(2), 255. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14020255