Parmenides as a Thinker of Fate
Abstract
:1. Introduction
His mysterious vision in the realm of light is a genuine religious experience: when the weak human eye turns towards the hidden truth, life itself becomes transfigured. This is a kind of experience that has no place in the religion of the official cults. Its prototype is rather to be sought in the devotions we find in the mysteries and initiation ceremonies; […] we encounter a highly individual inner experience of the Divine, combined with the fervour of a devotee who feels himself charged with proclaiming the truths of his own personal revelation and who seeks to establish a community of the faithful among his converts.
2. The Discovery of Parmenides
3. Fatal Necessity
See these things, which, remote though they are, are firmly present to thought.
For you will not cut off what is from cohering with what is,
Whether it is dispersed completely everywhere throughout the world
Or is collected together.22
[…] οὐδ’ οἷ χρόνος ἐστίν, ἤ ἔσται/ἄλλο πάρεξ τοῦ ἐόντος, ἐπεὶ τό γε Μοῖρ’ ἐπέδησεν/οὖλον ἀκίνητόν τ’ ἔμεναι· τῶι πάντ’ ὀνόμαστι…
Und für dies gibt es keine Zeit, oder es wird/etwas anderes außer dem Seienden geben, da eben dies Moira gebunden hat, ganz und unbeweglich zu sein. Damit werden alle [Dinge] bezeichnet…
And for this there is no time, or there will be/anything other than ‘what is,’ since Moira has bound even this, so that it is a whole and something immovable. By this, all [things] are named…23
4. Understanding the Unity of All Things
5. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Παρμενίδης […] πάντα κατ’ ἀνάγκην· τὴν αὐτὴν δ’ εἶναι εἱμαρμένην καὶ δίκην καὶ πρόνοιαν καὶ κοσμοποιόν (DK 28 A 32; LM 19 R 55a). In this paper I will use the abbreviation DK for Diels and Kranz (1951–1975) and LM for Laks and Most (2016); here I use LM’s translation. There are other testimonies not collected by DK which attributes a doctrine of fate to Parmenides, such as, for instance, Plutarchus, De animae procreatione in Timaeo, 1026b; Theodoretus, Graecarum affectionum curatio, VI, 13 (LM 19 R 55b). |
2 | See DK 28 B 1, 29; 2, 4: LM 19 D 4, 29; 6, 4. |
3 | For an exploration of the composition of the Parmenides’ poem in relation to its precedents in epic literature, see Robbiano (2006, pp. 35–60) and Tulli (2016). |
4 | For the interaction among reason and myth in Parmenides’ thought see Morgan (2000, pp. 67–88). |
5 | My words are alluding to one of the meanings of νοεῖν in Homer: “[…] to realize or to understand a situation” (von Fritz 1943, p. 93). See also Lesher (1981, p. 15). It is obvious that the verb νοεῖν is very important in Parmenides’ discourse. |
6 | Παρμενίδης δέ μοι φαίνεται, τὸ τοῦ Ὁμήρου, “αἰδοῖός τέ μοι” εἶναι ἅμα “δεινός τε” (Plato, Theaet., 183e; Burnet 1900). See Ilias, III, 172; XVIII, 394; Odyssea, VIII, 22. |
7 | “Parménides se interesa por el contenido del verbo, por el hecho de ser, y afirma que este hecho se impone como una realidad indudable e insoslayable desde el momento en que… se es” (Cordero 2007, p. 271). See also Cordero (2004, pp. 64–69). |
8 | In this respect, the following words of Vlastos (1970, pp. 83–84) are illuminating: “When Parmenldes speaks of Dike-Ananke holding Being fast in the bonds of the limit, his words echo Hesiod and Semonides, who speak of fate as a ‘bond of unbreakable fetters’; but his thought is far from theirs. In Hesiod and Semonides the source of the compulsion is external to the thing compelled. In Parmenides the compulsion is immanent. The first is a non-rational concept of ananke: the determining agency remains hidden from human reason. The second is so thoroughly rational that ananke merges with dike, and dike with logicophysical necessity: the order of nature is deducible from the intelligible properties of nature itself.” |
9 | See above all DK 28 B 8, 8-11.26-30.43-45; LM 19 D 8, 13-16.31-35.48-50. |
10 | Doxography has pointed out such a denial of appearances: see DK 28 A 25; LM 19 R 47; Plutarchus, Adversus Colotem, 1114c–f, etc. |
11 | Μοῖρα: DK 28 B 8, 37; LM 19 D 8, 42; Δίκη: DK 28 B 8, 14; LM 19 D 8, 19 (see also DK 28 B 1, 14.28; LM 19 D 14.28). Compare with Ἀνάγκη: DK 28 B 8, 30; B 10, 6; LM 19 D 8, 35; D 12, 6 (see also DK 28 B 8, 16; LM 19 D 8, 21). |
12 | The author of the Derveni Papyrus also indicates that different proper names of various divinities are but appellatives belonging to a single god: cf. LM 30, col. 21, 7. Robinson (2008, p. 493) suggests that Parmenides’ Moira could be even identified with Zeus. |
13 | χρεώ (DK 28 B 1, 28; LM 19 D 4, 28), χρῆν (DK 28 B 1, 32; LM 19 D 4, 32), χρεών (DK 28 B 2, 5; B 8, 11.45; LM 19 D 6, 5; D 8, 16.50), χρή (DK 28 B 6, 1; LM 19 D 7, 1), χρέος (DK 28 B 8, 9; LM 19 D 8, 14). |
14 | “No hay dos maneras de ser: se es o no se es. No hay grados de ser. Por eso dice Parménides que lo que es es único y completo (fragmento 8.6)” (Cordero 2007, p. 283). |
15 | See DK 28 B 8, 5–6.21.27; LM 19 D 8, 10–11.26.32. |
16 | This interpretation was already proposed by Simplicius: see DK 28 A 20; LM 19 R 5b. |
17 | See DK 28 B 1, 29; LM 19 D 4, 29. In fact, LM discard DK’s reading of the “roundness” (εὐκυκλέος) of truth and prefer to understand truth as “well-convincing” (εὐπειθέος), as Mourelatos (2008, pp. 154–58) had already proposed. |
18 | Τὸ μὲν οὖν εἶναι τὸ ὂν ὅταν ᾖ, καὶ τὸ μὴ ὂν μὴ εἶναι ὅταν μὴ ᾖ, ἀνάγκη (De interpr., 19a23–24; Minio-Paluello 1949). My translation. |
19 | See DK 28 B 8, 5; LM 19 D 8, 10. For this reason, Parmenides’ ἐόν has been characterized with eternity, ἀίδιον (DK 28 A 22–23; LM 19 R 29–30), although he does not use that term: see DK 28 A 30 (a testimony which does not appear in LM). |
20 | That in this passage Aristotle argues with the Megarics has been repeatedly proposed by critics (Weidemann 2014, pp. 53–54). On the Eleatic background of Megaric philosophy, see Mársico (2012). The problems raised by Cambiano (1977) about the very existence of a Megaric school and its Eleatic filiation do not affect my argument, since what interests us here is the fact that the quoted passage of Aristotle (De interpr., 19a23–24) reveals some reflection on the thought of Parmenides. In any case, the modal question raised in it is certainly linked to the one expressed in Metaph. Θ, 3, 1046b29–32 with an unclear mention of certain “Megarics.” |
21 | DK 28 B 8, 32; LM 19 D 8, 37. |
22 | λεῦσσε δ’ ὅμως ἀπεόντα νόῳ παρεόντα βεβαίως·/οὐ γὰρ ἀποτμήξει τὸ ἐὸν τοῦ ἐόντος ἔχεσθαι/οὔτε σκιδνάμενον πάντηι πάντως κατὰ κόσμον/οὔτε συνιστάμενον (DK 28 B 4; LM 19 D 10). LM’s translation. |
23 | My English translation of Marcinkowska-Rosół’s version. For the Greek text, see DK 28 B 8, 36–38; LM 19 D 8, 40–43. |
24 | This interpretation of time as a timeless present is also favoured by Owen (1993), Rapp (2007, p. 119) and Conte (2024, pp. 31 and 43). For a noteworthy critique of this view, see O’Brien (1980). |
25 | Curd (2011) has argued more vehemently than I’m going to do here for the discontinuity between sensation and νόος, but she believes that the proper object of νόος, unlike sensation, is Being. However, if Parmenides did not think that the senses do grasp Being (albeit only partially), then he would have affirmed that they do not inform us of anything; indeed, there would be no sensibility at all. |
26 | νῦν ἔστιν ὁμοῦ πᾶν (DK 28 B 8, 5; LM 19 D 8, 10). |
27 | See DK 28 B 4; LM 19 D 10. |
28 | See DK 28 B 12, 3; B 13; B 18, 1; LM 19 D 14b, 3; D 16; D 49, 1; R 56b. |
29 | “Alle Dinge sind verkettet, verfädelt, verliebt” (Nietzsche 1988, p. 402). Despite the carachteristic ‘creativity’ of his understanding of the Presocratics in Nietzsche’s youthful lectures, published under the title Die Philosophie im tragischen Zeitalter der Griechen, the fatalistic interpretation of Parmenides that I am giving does not appear there, although it is undoubtedly quite close to the personal philosophy of the German philosopher. |
References
- Barnes, Jonathan. 1982. The Presocratic Philosophers. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Bernabé, Alberto. 2004. Textos órficos y filosofía presocrática. Materiales para una comparación. Madrid: Trotta. [Google Scholar]
- Burnet, John. 1900. Platonis opera. Oxford: Clarendon Press, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Calogero, Guido. 1977. Studi sull’Eleatismo. Firenze: La nuova Italia. [Google Scholar]
- Cambiano, Giuseppe. 1977. Il problema dell’esistenza di una scuola Megarica. In Scuole socratiche minori e filosofia ellenistica. Edited by Gabriele Giannantoni. Bologna: Il Mulino, pp. 25–53. [Google Scholar]
- Conte, Bruno L. 2024. A Necessidade e outras divindades no poema de Parmênides. In Filosofía y religión en la Grecia antigua. Edited by Jorge Luis Gutiérrez, David Torrijos Castrillejo, Andrea da Paz, Luiz Eduardo Freitas and Pedro Maurício Garcia Dotto. Salamanca and Madrid: UPSA Ediciones/Sindéresis. [Google Scholar]
- Cordero, Néstor-Luis. 2004. By Being, It Is. The Thesis of Parmenides. Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Cordero, Néstor-Luis. 2007. Epílogo al Poema de Parménides. In Parménides. Poema. Fragmentos y tradición textual. Edited by Alberto Bernabé and Jorge Pérez de Tudela. Madrid: Istmo, pp. 263–85. [Google Scholar]
- Coxon, Allan H. 2009. The Fragments of Parmenides. A Critical Text with Introduction and Translation, the Ancient Testimonia and a Commentary. Edited by Richard McKirahan. Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Curd, Patricia. 2004. The Legacy of Parmenides. Princeton: Princeton UP. [Google Scholar]
- Curd, Patricia. 2011. Divinity and Intelligibility in Parmenides. In Ontologia Scienza Mito: Per una Nuova Lettura di Parmenide. Edited by Luigi Riggiu and Carlo Natali. Milano: Mimesis, pp. 117–33. [Google Scholar]
- Diels, Hermann, and Walther Kranz. 1951–1975. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. Berlin: Weidmann. [Google Scholar]
- Döring, Klaus. 1972. Die Megariker: Kommentierte Sammlung der Testimonien. Amsterdam: B. R. Grüner. [Google Scholar]
- Drozdek, Adam. 2007. Greek Philosophers as Theologians: The Divine Arche. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Gallop, David. 1984. Parmenides of Elea. Fragments: A Text and Translation with an Introduction. Toronto, Buffalo and London: University of Toronto Press. [Google Scholar]
- García-Lorente, José Antonio. 2023. El ocaso de la metafísica en el siglo XXI a partir de Aristóteles y Platón. Carthaginensia: Revista de estudios e investigación 39: 595–618. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Greene, William Chase. 1944. Mοira: Fate, Good, and Evil in Greek Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Guthrie, William K. Ch. 1965. A History of Greek Philosophy. Volume II: The Presocratic Tradition from Parmenides to Democritus. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. [Google Scholar]
- Jaeger, Werner. 1947. The Theology of Early Greek Philosophers. Oxford: Clarendon. [Google Scholar]
- Laks, André, and Glenn W. Most. 2016. Early Greek Philosophy. Cambridge and London: Harvard UP. [Google Scholar]
- Lesher, James H. 1981. Perceiving and Knowing in the Iliad and Odyssey. Phronesis 26: 2–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- MacFarlane, John. 2000. Aristotle’s Definition of Anagnorisis. American Journal of Philology 121: 367–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Magris, Aldo. 2008. Destino, provvidenza, predestinazione: Dal mondo antico al cristianesimo. Brescia: Morcelliana. [Google Scholar]
- Mansfeld, Jaap. 2015. Parmenides from Right to Left. Études platoniciennes 12. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Marcinkowska-Rosół, Maria. 2010. Die Konzeption des ›Noein‹ bei Parmenides von Elea. Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mársico, Claudia. 2012. Megaric Philosophy Between Socrates’ Influence and Parmenides’ Ghost. In Parmenides, Venerable and Awesome. Edited by Néstor-Luis Cordero. Las Vegas, Zurich and Athens: Parmenides Publishing, pp. 353–61. [Google Scholar]
- Mársico, Claudia. 2013. Socráticos. Testimonios y fragmentos. Buenos Aires: Losada. [Google Scholar]
- Minio-Paluello, Lorenzo. 1949. Aristotelis categoriae et liber de interpretatione. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Morgan, Kathryn A. 2000. Myth and Philosophy from the Presocratics to Plato. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mourelatos, Alexander P. D. 2008. The Route of Parmenides. Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Neuman Lorenzini, Rosario, and David Torrijos Castrillejo. 2023. Heráclito y la vía de la interioridad. Co-Herencia: Revista de Humanidades 20: 231–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1988. Also sprach Zarathustra. In Sämtliche Werke. Edited by Giorgio Colli and Mazzino Montinari. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, vol. 4. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nietzsche, Friedrich. 2005. Thus Spoke Zarathustra: A Book for Everyone and Nobody. Edited by Graham Parkes. New York: Oxford UP. [Google Scholar]
- O’Brien, Denis. 1980. Temps et intemporalité chez Parménide. Les Études Philosophiques 3: 257–72. [Google Scholar]
- O’Brien, Denis. 2012. Parménide. In Lire les présocratiques. Edited by Luc Brisson, Arnaud Macé and Anne-Laure Therme. Paris: PUF, pp. 129–48. [Google Scholar]
- Oriol Salgado, Manuel. 2023. Aristóteles, el mal moral y el pecado. Cauriensia 18: 507–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Owen, Gwilym E. L. 1993. Plato and Parmenides on the Timeless Present. In The Pre-Socratics: A Collection of Critical Essays. Edited by Alexander P. D. Mourelatos. Princeton: Princeton UP, pp. 271–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Palmer, John. 2009. Parmenides and Presocratic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford UP. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rapp, Christof. 2007. Vorsokratiker. München: Beck. [Google Scholar]
- Robbiano, Chiara. 2006. Becoming Being. On Parmenides’ Transformative Philosophy. Sankt Augustin: Academia. [Google Scholar]
- Robinson, Thomas M. 2008. Presocratic Theology. In The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Edited by Patricia Curd and Daniel W. Graham. Oxford: Oxford UP, pp. 485–99. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Torrijos-Castrillejo, David. 2014. Anaxágoras y su recepción en Aristóteles. Roma: EDUSC. [Google Scholar]
- Tulli, Mauro. 2016. Strategien der Erzählung und der Überzeugung des Adressaten bei Parmenides. In Philosophus Orator. Rhetorische Strategien und Strukturen in Philosophischer Literatur. Edited by Irmgard Mannlein-Robert, Wolfgang Rother, Stefan Schorn and Christian Tornau. Basel: Schwabe, pp. 31–46. [Google Scholar]
- Vlastos, Gregory. 1970. Equality and Justice in Early Greek Cosmologies. In Studies in Presocratic Philosophy: Volume 1: The Beginnings of Philosophy. Edited by David Furley and Reginald E. Allen. New York: Humanities Press, pp. 56–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- von Fritz, Kurt. 1943. NOOΣ and NOEIN in the Homeric Poems. Classical Philology 38: 79–93. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Warren, James. 2007. Presocratics. Stockfield: Acumen. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Weidemann, Hermann. 2014. Aristoteles Peri hermeneias. Boston and Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. [Google Scholar]
- West, Martin L. 2013. Towards Monotheism. In Hellenica: Selected Papers on Greek Literature and Thought. Volume III: Philosophy, Music and Metre, Literary Byways, Varia. Edited by Martin L. West. Oxford: Oxford UP, pp. 3–23. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Torrijos-Castrillejo, D. Parmenides as a Thinker of Fate. Religions 2024, 15, 1295. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15111295
Torrijos-Castrillejo D. Parmenides as a Thinker of Fate. Religions. 2024; 15(11):1295. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15111295
Chicago/Turabian StyleTorrijos-Castrillejo, David. 2024. "Parmenides as a Thinker of Fate" Religions 15, no. 11: 1295. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15111295
APA StyleTorrijos-Castrillejo, D. (2024). Parmenides as a Thinker of Fate. Religions, 15(11), 1295. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15111295