Transcending Individual Traditions: Zhang Taiyan’s Interpretation of Zhuangzi’s Notion of Chengxin
Abstract
:1. Introduction
If we are to follow chengxin as a guide, then who does not have such a guide? Not only those who know the change in nature and adhere to it have them, but stupid people have theirs too. To have opinions as to right or wrong before establishing something in your heart-mind is as mistaken as to say that “one goes to the state of Yue today and arriving there yesterday”.3
2. Overview of Previous Interpretations of Zhuangzi’s Chengxin
2.1. Daoist Interpretations of Chengxin
A mind that is sufficient to control the activities of a single person is called the “formed mind”. As people make the formed mind their own teachers, everyone has a teacher for himself. Since each person has his own teacher, he trusts in it and so considers himself correct.
To exchange the unformed for the formed is not how knowing works, for the mind gets from itself. Therefore, the stupid also make their formed minds their teachers, never willing to use what they refer to as “shortcomings” [of others] and discard what they refer to as [their own] “strengths”.
If one were to go to Yue today, how could one arrive yesterday? If not first formed in the mind, where could right and wrong come from? It is obvious that right and wrong as such are things that all kinds of people can’t do without. Therefore, the Perfected one [zhiren] follows along the course of both.
Those who limit their view to a narrow scope and cling to the biases of one perspective are said to have a formed mind. The mind that follows and adheres to these fixed views considers them as standards; this is how the world operates, so who can claim to be without a teacher?
Those who are foolish and confused stubbornly insist on right and wrong. They do not need to understand others’ strengths to compensate for their own weaknesses; they only seek to criticize others as inferior and assert their own superiority. Such people are found everywhere, and the truly ignorant are often the first among them.
2.2. Neo-Confucian Interpretations of Chengxin
The mind of the Perfected one is as tranquil as a mirror, not dependent on external conditions but complete within itself. … I have not achieved this completed mind, hence I am bewildered. Those Perfected one, however, are free from bewilderment. … The completed mind is what I receive from Heaven without deficiency, thus enabling me to clearly distinguish the true from the false.
Chengxin refers to the heavenly principle inherent in everyone, regarded as complete and universal. All beings are endowed with this inherent principle of heaven. … However, if one’s mind fails to recognize this unified principle and instead clings to rigid distinctions between right and wrong … it is akin to traveling to the state of Yue today but arriving there yesterday. … Such conduct is called pretending to know when one does not truly understand.
3. Zhang Taiyan’s Yogācāra Interpretation of Chengxin
3.1. Zhang Taiyan and His Qiwulun Shi
3.2. Zhuangzi’s Chengxin and Seeds in the Ālaya-vijñāna
The pipes of Heaven producing sounds by blowing through the myriad things metaphorically represent the ālaya-vijñāna (Storehouse Consciousness). “The myriad things” symbolize all the seeds within the ālaya-vijñāna, which are termed “innate ideas” in modern times. Seeds cover not only words/concepts but also the fundamental qualities of attributes; hence the text says: “blow through the myriad things differently”. The phrase “allow them all to act on their own” suggests it is only be virtue of being grounded in the ālaya-vijñāna that the faculty of mind attaches itself to this consciousness and treats it as the “self”.
When the six sensory consciousnesses of the eye, ear, nose, tongue, body, and mind are quiescent, chengxin resides latent in the storehouse consciousness and the mental consciousness. Upon their activation, chengxin emerges spontaneously and appropriately, without requiring external instruction. This is what is meant by “following the chengxin as one’s teacher.”
3.3. Comparison with Previous Interpretations
3.3.1. Comparison of Zhang’s and Daoist Interpretations
3.3.2. Comparison of Zhang’s and Neo-Confucian Interpretations
4. Theoretical Underpinning of Zhang’s Interpretation
The meaning of “inherent awakening” is spoken of in relation to the meaning of initial awakening since initial awakening is precisely the same as inherent awakening. The meaning of “initial awakening” is this: because of inherent awakening, there is non-awakening; and because of non-awakening, one speaks of there being initial awakening.
It is because all the characteristics of the mind and consciousnesses are ignorance and, since the characteristic of ignorance is not separate from the nature of awakening, the mind and consciousnesses are both indestructible and destructible.
Its thought-moments lack intrinsic characteristics and are not apart from inherent awakening. This is just like a disoriented person, who becomes disoriented because there are directions. Once apart from directions, there is no becoming disoriented. Sentient beings are also like this: they become disoriented because there is awakening. Once apart from awakening, there is no non-awakening.
5. Criticisms and Implications of Zhang’s Interpretation
5.1. Criticisms of Zhang’s Interpretation
5.2. Implications of Zhang’s Interpretation
6. Conclusions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | See (Mou 2023). In Mou’s view, central to the alternative religious experience embodied by the three teachings is the pursuit of personal cultivation. These three distinct yet interrelated ways of thinking and living form a moral ecology. Each complements the others, serving different dimensions of the human need for an educated spirituality. Mou views these three distinct yet harmonious philosophies as forming a moral ecosystem, where each complements the others, addressing various facets of human spiritual growth. |
2 | Chinese philosophical terms are typically polysemous, and this reflects the rich, complex, fluid, and interchanging experiences that Chinese philosophers attempted to understand in their own persons, communities, personal lives, and public duties as well as the myriad fellow beings and the universe they share together in a common destiny. |
3 | The translations are my own, with references to Chan (1963, p. 182), Chong (2011), and Lynn (2022, p. 26). |
4 | For more on this, see Assandri (2019). This article shows, for the case of Cheng Xuanying, how terminological overlap with contemporary Buddhist authors indicates that Buddhists and Daoists both participated in the discourse on inner cultivation with commentaries to their respective sacred scriptures. |
5 | Translations are my own unless stated otherwise. |
6 | Lynn (2022, p. xlviii) classified Guo Xiang’s position as one of “immanent monism”: “Guo insists that no external generator exists because for him, no existence is possible apart from material reality; as such, designations such as Heaven [tian], Dao, Creator [zaowuzhe], or Great Ultimate [taiji] refer not to any universal principle transcendent to physical reality but to one immanent in everything. … It follows that since the Dao is inherent in all things, it is identical with both their self-generation [zisheng] and self-transformation [zihua]”. In Guo‘s commentary, the term tianli also appears, but it differs from the concept of “universal principle transcendent to physical reality”; rather, it refers to the natural order. For instance, in his commentary on the Qi wu lun, Guo states, “rulers and subjects, superiors and inferiors, hands and feet, and the outer and the inner are all results of spontaneous workings of natural principle [tianli ziran]” (Lynn 2022, p. 24). |
7 | The Ālaya-vijñāna, also known as the Ādāna-vñāna, is referred to as the “storehouse consciousness” due to its function of containing or storing seeds. Zhang Taiyan identifies the storehouse consciousness with the Tathāgatagarbha, the “womb” or “embryo” of the Tathāgata. |
8 | To my knowledge, there is only one Korean-language article that specifically addresses this topic. The article underscores Zhang’s advocacy for communication that recognizes differences and grapples with the tensions between tradition and modernity, or between China and the West (Kim 2018). |
9 | The translations are my own, with reference to Makeham (2012, p. 121). |
10 | Mind is another term for ālaya-vijñāna, as it both stores and gives rise to all seeds of phenomena and knowledge. It is called seeds mind, because from it spring all individualities, or particulars. |
11 | The Cheng Weishi Lun (Treatise on the Establishment of Consciousness-Only) elucidates the definition and reality of seeds: “What kind of dharma is called Bija? The Bijas are the different potentialities which are found in the Mulavijnana, root-consciousness, i.e., the Alayavijnana, and which immediately engender their fruit, that is to say, the actual dharmas (i.e., dharmas in activity). The Bijas, in relation to the root-consciousness and the fruit, are neither identical nor different. Such is, in reality, the mode of relation between the substance (svabhava), consciousness, and the activity (karitra), Bija; between the cause (hetu), Bija, and the fruit (phala), actual dharma” (Wei 1973, p. 109). |
12 | Names denote verbal expressions, and phenomena refer to the objects perceived by sensations, perceptions, and mental activities, also known in Buddhism as “phenomenal appearances” (Skt. ālambana). They specifically denote various conditioned phenomena including colors, sounds, smells, tastes, and tactile sensations. |
13 | According to Plato, each category of entities possesses its own distinct form, which accounts for the diversity observed in the world. The totality of these forms constitutes what Plato termed the world of “forms” or “ideas”. |
14 | Jiang (2002, p. 491) distinguishes the difference between the concepts held by Kant and Zhang Taiyan: “For Kant, pure concepts exist a priori, while for Zhang Binglin, innate ideas are the subjective products of human mental activity”. However, in my view, Zhang’s concept of innate ideas encompasses both those that exist a priori and those that are the subjective products of human mental activity. |
15 | The temporal, spatial, and numerical consciousnesses are mentioned in the Mahāyāna-samgraha. Temporal consciousness encompasses the understanding of past, present, and future. Spatial consciousness pertains to dimensions such as point, line, surface, solid, center, edge, and orientation. Form consciousness encompasses considerations of form, sound, touch, smell, and taste. |
16 | Fraser (2023, p. 92) characterizes the governance of the sagely ruler as one who navigates an undifferentiated expanse, eschewing fixed paths or personal biases: “The ruler is instead to govern as if ‘wandering’ through a plain, undifferentiated vastness—and thus following no particular path or direction—setting aside personal views of how things should be. The crux is to conform to people’s own tendencies and activity. … A ruler who can flow along with the people’s existing propensities finds that society is already in good order, in and of itself”. |
17 | In the Mawangdui silk manuscripts of the Laozi, the sentence exhibits a divergent word order, rendered as “Shengren chang wu xin 聖人常無心”, which literally translates to “the sage constantly has no mind”, in contrast to the more conventional formulation “Shengren wu chang xin 聖人無常心”, which literally means “the sage has no constant mind”. Nevertheless, the semantic implications of both versions remain largely equivalent. |
18 | The four investigations include the investigation of name (nāmaparyesanā); the investigation of object-base (vastuparyesanā); the investigation of the designation of intrinsic nature (svabhāvaprajñaptiparyesanā), and the investigation of the designation of differences (viśesaprajñaptiparyesanā). |
19 | The word tian ni is translated as “the Heavenly Equality” (Watson 1968, p. 48), “the whetstone of Heaven” (Graham 1981, p. 60), or “the framework of nature” (Mair 1994, p. 23). |
20 | “Supreme tian ni” refers to the wisdom of reality derived from the transformation of consciousness into wisdom. |
21 | Vāsanā refers to habitual patterns of thought, speech, or action that are imprinted in the mind. In the Yogācāra school, vāsanā, often used synonymously with bīja (‘seed’), is imprinted in the ālaya-vijñāna. The three kinds of perfuming influence are image (nimitta), name (nama), and discriminating influence (vikalpavasana). |
22 | In Yogācāra Buddhism, as certain perspectives propose, the seeds within the ālaya-vijñāna are basically divided into two types, according to their origins. The Cheng Weishi Lun (Treatise on the Establishment of Consciousness-Only) elucidates Dharmapala’s view on this matter, delineating the classification as follows: “Bijas are of two kinds: 1. Natural or inborn Bijas: these refer to the potentialities which have innately existed since before the beginning of time. … 2. Bijas whose existence has had a beginning: these Bijas have come into being as a result of perfuming (vāsanā) by actual dharmas....These Bijas are called ‘Bijas born by reason of perfuming’” (Wei 1973, p. 116). |
23 | Seeds in the mind, particularly the attachment to the self, serve as the barriers to enlightenment. However, obstacles and enlightenment are inherently interconnected. Supreme enlightenment is achieved only when all forms of ignorance and suffering have been completely dispelled. |
24 | The formal and causal consciousness within the seven types of seeds have no basis in Yogācāra and may have been introduced by Zhang in contrast to Kant. |
25 | The Western concept of “innate ideas” finds its roots in Plato’s theory of “forms” or “ideas”. Plato proposed that beyond the ever-changing material world perceived through our senses exists a realm of perfect, eternal forms. |
26 | In Kantian philosophy, the twelve a priori categories represent pure concepts of the understanding and are essential for organizing empirical judgments about objects of experience. These a priori categories of pure reason correspond to the concept of innate ideas Zhang adopted. |
References
- Assandri, Friederike. 2019. Conceptualizing the Interaction of Buddhism and Daoism in the Tang Dynasty: Inner Cultivation and Outer Authority in the Daode Jing Commentaries of Cheng Xuanying and Li Rong. Religions 10: 66. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cai, Zhidong 蔡志棟. 2013. Zhang Taiyan Houqi Zhexue Sixiang Yanjiu 章太炎後期哲學思想研究 [A Study on Zhang Taiyan’s Later Philosophical Thoughts]. Shanghai: Shanghai Academy of Social Sciences Press. [Google Scholar]
- Chan, Wing-Tsit. 1963. A Source Book of Chinese Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Chang, Hao. 1987. Chinese Intellectuals in Crisis: Search for Order and Meaning (1890–1911). Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Chen, Shaoming 陳少明. 2003. Dispelling the Illusions of Names and Form: Study on Zhang Taiyan’s Qiwulun Shi 排遣名相之後——章太炎《齊物論釋》研究. Philosophical Researches 哲學研究 5: 31–38. [Google Scholar]
- Chong, Kim-chong. 2006. Zhuangzi and the Nature of Metaphor. Philosophy East and West 56: 370–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chong, Kim-chong. 2011. Zhuangzi’s Cheng Xin and its Implications for Virtue and Perspectives. Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 10: 427–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chung, Julianne Nicole. 2018. Is Zhuangzi a Fictionalist? Philosophers’ Imprint 18: 1–23. [Google Scholar]
- D’Ambrosio, Paul Joseph. 2023. Guo Xiang’s Metaphysics of Being and Action: On the Importance of Xing 性. Religions 14: 879. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fraser, Chris. 2023. Late Classical Chinese Thought. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Fung, Yu-lan. 1948. A Short History of Chinese Philosophy. New York: Free Press. [Google Scholar]
- Graham, A. C., trans. 1981. Chuang-tzu—The Seven Inner Chapters and Other Writings from the Book Chuang-tzu. London: George Allen & Unwin. [Google Scholar]
- Guo, Xiang 郭象, and Xuanying Cheng 成玄英. 2011. Zhuangzi Zhushu 莊子注疏 [Commentary and Sub-commentary on the Zhuangzi]. Beijing: Zhonghua Book Company 中華書局. [Google Scholar]
- Hong, C. Lynne. 2022. The Zhuangzi and Buddhism. In Dao Companion to the Philosophy of the Zhuangzi. Edited by Kim-chong Chong. Cham: Springer, pp. 467–91. [Google Scholar]
- Ishii, Tsuyoshi 石井剛. 2014. The Philosophy of Qiwu: Zhang Taiyan and the Encounter between Chinese Modern Thoughts and East Asia 齊物的哲學:章太炎與中國現代思想的東亞經驗. Shanghai: East China Normal University Press 華東師範大學出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Jiang, Hainu 蔣海怒. 2012. Wanqing Zhengzhi yu Foxue 晚清政治與佛學 [Politics and Buddhism in the Late Qing China]. Shanghai: Shanghai Ancient Books Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jiang, Tao. 2016. The Problem of Authorship and the Project of Chinese Philosophy: Zhuang Zhou and the Zhuangzi between Sinology and Philosophy in the Western Academy. Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 15: 35–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jiang, Yihua 姜義華. 2002. Zhang Binlin Pingzhuan 章炳麟評傳 [Biography of Zhang Binglin]. Nanjing: Nanjing University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jorgensen, John, Dan Lusthaus, John Makeham, and Mark Strange, trans. 2019. Treatise on Awakening Mahāyāna Faith. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kim, Young-jin 김영진. 2018. Zhang Taiyan’s Interpretation of Cheng-xin in Qiwulun-Shi and the Theory of Seeds 장태염 (章太炎) 제물론석 (齊物論釋) 의 ‘성심 (成心)’ 해석과 종자설. Journal of Chinese Studies 중국학보 83: 242–64. [Google Scholar]
- Lee, Mabel. 2013. Zhang Taiyan: Daoist Individualism and Political Reality. Frontiers of Literary Studies in China 7: 346–66. [Google Scholar]
- Lin, Xiyi 林希逸. 1997. Zhuangzi Yanzhai Kouyi Jiaozhu 莊子鬳齋口義校注 [Yanzhai’s Annotation and Commentary on the Zhuangzi]. Beijing: Zhonghua Book Company 中華書局. [Google Scholar]
- Lü, Huiqing 吕惠卿. 2009. Zhuangzi Yi Jijiao 莊子義集校 [Assembled Collations and Commentary on the Zhuangzi]. Beijing: Zhonghua Book Company 中華書局. [Google Scholar]
- Lynn, Richard John. 2022. Zhuangzi: A New Translation of the Sayings of Master Zhuang as Interpreted by Guo Xiang. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Machek, David. 2010. Is Freedom in Necessity or in Happiness? The Controversy between Guo Xiang’s and Lin Xiyi’s Interpretation of Zhuangzi’s Free Rambling. Studia Orientalia Slovaca 9: 111–28. [Google Scholar]
- Mair, Victor, trans. 1994. Wandering on the Way—Early Taoist Tales and Parables of Chuang Tzu. Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press. [Google Scholar]
- Makeham, John. 2012. Zhang Taiyan, Yogācāra Buddhism and Chinese Philosophy. In Learning to Emulate the Wise: The Genesis of Chinese Philosophy as an Academic Discipline in Twentieth-Century China. Edited by John Makeham. Hong Kong: Chinese University of Hong Kong Press. [Google Scholar]
- Meng, Zhuo 孟琢. 2019. Qiwulun Shi Shuzheng 齊物論釋疏證 [Commentary on An Interpretation of Discourse on Making All Things Equal]. Shanghai: Shanghai People’s Press 上海人民出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Mou, Zhongjian. 2023. A Brief History of the Relationship between Confucianism, Daoism, and Buddhism. Singapore: Springer Nature. [Google Scholar]
- Murthy, Viren. 2014. Equality as Reification: Zhang Taiyan’s Yogācāra Reading of Zhuangzi in the Context of Global Modernity. In Transforming Consciousness: Yogacara Thought in Modern China. Edited by John Makeham. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Shi, Dixian 釋諦閑. 2014. Tiantaizong jiangyi 天台宗講義 [Lectures on the Tiantai School]. Shanghai: East China Normal University Press 華東師範大學出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Su, Meiwen 蘇美文. 2007. Zhang Taiyan Qiwulun Shi Yanjiu 章太炎《齊物論釋》研究 [Study on Zhang Taiyan’s Qiwulun Shi]. New Taipei City: Huamulan Culture Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Xiaojie 王曉潔. 2022. Zhang Taiyan Qiwulun Shi Zhexue Sixiang Yanjiu 章太炎《齊物論釋》哲學思想研究 [The Research on Zhang Taiyan’s Philosophical Thought of Qiwulun Shi]. Beijing: People’s Press. [Google Scholar]
- Watson, Burton, trans. 1968. The Complete Works of Chuang Tzu. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wei, Tat. 1973. Ch’eng wei-shih lun: The Doctrine of Mere-Consciousness. Hong Kong: Ch’eng Wei-shih Lun Publication Committee. [Google Scholar]
- Xie, Ming-Yang. 2005. An Investigation on Differing Interpretations of the Concept of “Cheng-Xin” in the Old Annotations of the “Qi Wu Lun”. Dong Hwa Journal of Chinese Studies 3: 23–49. [Google Scholar]
- Zhang, Taiyan. 2011. Zhuohan weiyan 菿漢微言 [Zhang Taiyan’s Subtle Words]. Shanghai: Shanghai Shudian Chubanshe 上海書店出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Zhang, Taiyan. 2014. Qiwulun shi dingben 齊物論釋定本 [Definitive Edition of Interpretation of Discourse on Making All Things Equal]. In Zhang Taiyan Quanji 章太炎全集 [Collected Works of Zhang Taiyan]. Shanghai: Shanghai People’s Press 上海人民出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Zhang, Yaonan 張耀南, and Shuang Qian 錢爽. 2019. Free from the Four Lemmas, Cutting off the One Hundred Negations and Cheng Xuanying’s Study of Twofold Arcane “離四句絕百非”與成玄英”重玄學”. Religious Studies 宗教學研究 3: 29–33. [Google Scholar]
- Zürcher, Erik. 1980. Buddhist Influence on Early Taoism. T’oung Pao 66: 84–147. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Wang, C. Transcending Individual Traditions: Zhang Taiyan’s Interpretation of Zhuangzi’s Notion of Chengxin. Religions 2024, 15, 1309. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15111309
Wang C. Transcending Individual Traditions: Zhang Taiyan’s Interpretation of Zhuangzi’s Notion of Chengxin. Religions. 2024; 15(11):1309. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15111309
Chicago/Turabian StyleWang, Cheng. 2024. "Transcending Individual Traditions: Zhang Taiyan’s Interpretation of Zhuangzi’s Notion of Chengxin" Religions 15, no. 11: 1309. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15111309
APA StyleWang, C. (2024). Transcending Individual Traditions: Zhang Taiyan’s Interpretation of Zhuangzi’s Notion of Chengxin. Religions, 15(11), 1309. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15111309