The Talmudic Rabbi as Triage Officer: Decision-Making in Times of COVID-19
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. All Human Life Is Equal
If a woman is having trouble giving birth, they cut up the child in her womb and brings it forth limb by limb, because her life comes before the life of [the child]. But if the greater part has come out, one may not touch it, for one may not set aside one person’s life for that of another.8
3. Two Travelers in the Desert and One Bottle of Water
Two people were walking on a desolate path and there was a jug of water in the possession of one of them, [and the situation was such that] if both drink from the jug, both will die, but if only one of them drinks, he will reach a settled area. Ben Petura taught: It is preferable that both of them drink and die, and let neither one of them see the death of the other. [This was the accepted opinion] until Rabbi Akiba came and taught that the verse states: “And your brother shall live with you,” indicating that your life takes precedence over the life of the other.12
- Saving the life of one person permanently is to be preferred over saving the lives of several people temporarily. We should not divide the available resources among all patients equally but devote them to those lives that can be fully saved.
- One can also learn from this text (if one opposes the re-allocation of medical resources for ethical reasons) that once treatment of one patient has been started, the resources are in her possession and can no longer be taken away from her (as the water is already in the possession of one individual rather than the other).
- More radically, should somebody have said before the onset of our pericope: “I don’t need water in the desert, I don’t want to carry those heavy bottles, this restricts my personal freedom, this is my personal decision”, etc. (that is, if somebody is himself responsible for his COVID-19 infection, either by intentionally breaking social distance rules or by refusing to be vaccinated), he can be treated last, or with the lowest priority in allocating resources for that reason.14
4. Human Rights Trump Numbers
A number of Jews travelling on the road were attacked by a group of non-Jews who said: Give us one of you and we will kill him, if not, we will kill all of you. [The Talmud rules:] Even if all must die, do not surrender one soul from Israel.29
Reason tells us [the following ruling]: A certain person came before Raba and said to him: The lord of my place said to me: Go kill so-and-so, and if not, I will kill you, [what shall I do?] Raba said to him: [It is preferable that] he should kill you and you should not kill. Who is to say that your blood is redder [than his]? Perhaps that man’s blood is redder.33
5. Long-Term versus Short-Term Survival
Rabbi Yochanan said: If there is doubt as to life and death, a [Jewish] patient must not be treated by them [gentile doctors]. If it is certain that the patient will die, he can be treated [by gentile doctors]. [But even if it is certain that the patient will] die [if he is not treated], nevertheless, isn’t there is value in temporal life? We are not concerned with temporal life! And from where do you know that we are not concerned with temporal life? As it is written “If we say: We will enter into the city, then the famine is in the city, and we shall die there…” But isn’t there temporal life [to be lost]? Rather not, we are not concerned with temporal life!37
6. Summary
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Discussed, for example, here: https://www.nytimes.com/2020/03/21/us/coronavirus-medical-rationing.html (accessed on 18 August 2021). |
2 | The Hebrew Bible explicitly states, “I am the Eternal, your healer.” Ex 15:26, causing a debate of 2000 years within Judaism about the physician’s right to interfere, based on several other scriptural references. The majority opinion eventually not only accepted this right but declared the refusal to heal the sick to be bloodshed, based on Lev. 19:16. This view was even codified as binding law in the 16th century (ShA, YD 336). |
3 | See Kirschner (1985); Grodin et al. (2019). I will not include this rabbinic material in the present study as I confine the discussion to Talmudic literature. |
4 | |
5 | All of these Talmudic texts have been discussed before in connection with Jewish bioethics; I merely try to bring them into dialogue with some aspects of the COVID-19 pandemic. I will not refer, however, to later rabbinical sources, not even to responsa written on questions directly relating to COVID-19. For a good introduction to specifically Jewish answers to the involved ethical problems, see Dorff and Crane (2013). For advanced discussion, see Zohar (1997). |
6 | |
7 | |
8 | The translation is taken from Sefaria (https://www.sefaria.org.il/Mishnah_Oholot.8?lang=bi accessed on 2 January 2023). |
9 | In practical terms, the question here is whether, given that all other criteria are equal, a lottery is eventually an applicable triage method—a subject heavily discussed in bioethical literature. The Talmud seems to support this option. See White and Angus (2020). |
10 | In fact, this Mishnah is even more complex because even in the first case discussed in the text, when the baby is still within the body of her mother, this is already considered life, and we have to ask what difference partial birth is supposed to make here. While the Mishnah has been used to argue the Jewish view on abortion, in the COVID-19/triage/vaccination context under discussion in this essay, the unborn baby case is not relevant. |
11 | Bab. Talmud, Baba Meziah 62a and parallels. |
12 | Translation from Sefaria (https://www.sefaria.org.il/Bava_Metzia.62a.2?lang=bi&with=all&lang2=en accessed on 2 January 2023). |
13 | For an extensive and comprehensive discussion of this passage, including the Jewish reception history, especially in modern rabbinical thought, see Zoloth (1999). Interestingly, some modern Jewish thinkers side with Ben Petura, including Aaron Lichtenstein, Emanuel Levinas, Ernst Simon, and Louis Jacobs. |
14 | In Israel, there is an (unwritten) rule that even in the case of a multi-victim terrorist attack, the treatment of all wounded must be prioritized according to medical criteria, including that of the attacker. |
15 | In terms of COVID-19 vaccination debates, there was an interesting parallel to this tension when several countries received the first vaccine doses and had to make the following decision: Either use all available doses to vaccinate as many people as possible (and hope for more vaccine to arrive soon), or use only half of the received bottles, preserving the ability to give the already vaccinated the second dose three weeks later. Almost all countries did the latter. |
16 | Always prioritizing children over adults is a debated issue but not relevant to the COVID-19 pandemic. The counter-argument here is that children basically depend on the generation that cares for them, a thought that the Talmud would certainly support. |
17 | |
18 | Ex 22:21/Deut. 10:18/Deut. 27:19/Jer. 22:3/Zech. 7:10 and more. Hermann Cohen (1842–1918) has noted that with all our respect for the great cultural achievements of the ancient Greeks, the Hebrew prophets introduced an “epoch making turnaround” when they were not content with celebrating culture and philosophy as long as there was human suffering. This is what Cohen calls their “invention of the fellow human being (Mitmensch)” and the postulation of the duty to love her, none of which was as self-evident then as we tend to believe today. See Cohen, Der Begriff der Religion im System der Philosophie, Giessen 1915, pp. 75–76 (and other places). |
19 | Compare bT Succah 49b, Baba Batra 10a, Hullin 131a, and many more. |
20 | In Israel, early in 2021, high-ranking army officers were vaccinated before their soldiers—on the grounds of utility. |
21 | In Britain, the case of Lucy Watts, MBE, was heavily discussed in 2020. Watts is a prominent advocate for people with disabilities and health conditions, especially young people, having inspired thousands with her personal example. However, her own condition (respiratory muscle weakness) makes it unlikely she could survive IC for COVID-19, so she would be prioritized very low in case of triage if only medical criteria were considered. (https://www.bbc.com/news/disability-52149219 accessed on 2 January 2023). |
22 | bT Horayot 13a. The whole passage begins, however, with the statement that a man always precedes a woman when it comes to saving lives, which seems to contradict many other passages discussed in this paper. For discussion, see Rosner (2007). Jersey City 2007, pp. 172/173 and Zoloth, Health Care, pp. 168–71. |
23 | In March 2020, the case of Fr Berardelli, an Italian priest, caused much discussion. The 72-year-old was reported to have given a ventilator (that his parishioners had purchased for him) to a younger patient and subsequently died from COVID-19. Later, the story turned out to be untrue, but the ethical dispute about decisions of this kind remains interesting. (https://www.bbc.com/news/world-europe-52015969 accessed on 2 January 2023) Immanuel Kant, in the third formulation of the Categorical Imperative, explicitly included duties towards oneself, that is, to treat also yourself not as a means, but as an end in itself, which seems to exclude deliberate martyrdom, that is, giving up the water/ventilator for someone else. |
24 | End-of-life ethics in Judaism are a matter of dispute. A radical change was introduced here by Rabbi Moshe Feinstein in the 20th century when he ruled that a patient might not be forced to accept nutrition against his will (Iggrot Moshe, Hoshen Misphat 2, no. 74, for discussion Dorff/Crane, pp. 333–35). However, the Talmudic precedent for this and similar rulings is rare, and the available cases are rather strange and farfetched. See Newman (1990). |
25 | |
26 | Thompson, p. 1409. The other example given is a doctor who kills a person in order to harvest organs for five other people who are in urgent, life-saving need of transplantations. |
27 | Admittedly, a very strict utilitarian might be willing to accept the opposite option here. |
28 | For an extensive discussion of what he calls the “omission/commission distinction” in the context of the two-travelers text, see Zohar, Alternatives, pp. 103–6. |
29 | TJ, Trumot 47a. The same appears in Tosefta Trumot 7, 23. The Mishnah in Trumot (8, 12) has a slightly different version: Here it is about women threatened with rape, but I believe, given the other versions, the idea behind this text is more generally human, the way I discuss it in this paper. See Zoloth, Health Care, pp. 172/73. |
30 | This has sometimes been explained along the lines of ethnic belonging (“Jews don’t do that to each other”) because of the word Israel at the end of the passage. But again: I believe this passage conveys a stronger ethical message than tribal pride, self-defense, or even in-group solidarity. Here, it is interesting to compare this to the same problem mentioned in the Gospel of John (11:50), where the Jewish High Priest is said to have exclaimed: “Don’t you realize that it is better for you that one man die for the people than that the whole nation perish?” in order justify killing Jesus to appease the Romans. |
31 | This conclusion has been disputed, especially in the context of rabbinical responsa during the Holocaust. (See Dorff/Crane, p. 342, note 30.) The matter is too complex to be discussed sufficiently in this paper, however. In Kantian ethics, it seems to depend on the question of whether we refer to the Nazi soldiers (or to the Romans in the note above) as if they were an unstoppable train, a natural force, or if we still consider them human agents. |
32 | |
33 | Translation from Sefaria (https://www.sefaria.org.il/Sanhedrin.74a.20?lang=bi&with=all&lang2=en accessed on 2 January 2023). |
34 | |
35 | This latter option seems to be available from the famous ruling of Rabbi Feinstein (mentioned above) regarding end-of-life decisions. In cases where the patient herself wishes to end her life, the difference between withholding and withdrawing is indeed less relevant. See, for discussion, Dorff/Crane, pp. 334/335. |
36 | bT Avodah Zarah 27b. |
37 | Modified translation from Sefaria (https://www.sefaria.org.il/Avodah_Zarah.27b.4?lang=bi&with=all&lang2=en accessed on 2 January 2023). |
38 | Of course, the abstract solution is supported by our knowledge that the lepers find the city empty and full of food (II Kings 7:8). |
39 | bT San 78a. Maimonides codified this in the 12th century less leniently, but there are other commentators who continued the Talmudic line of thought: killing a trefah is killing a dead person (see Dorff/Crane, p. 335 and notes). |
40 | Here, our rabbi should be made aware of the fact that under Talmudic standards of medicine, death was in fact much easier to predict than today with modern medical science and artificial life-prolonging options (which is a problem in itself). |
41 | See the gruesome example from 1884 used by Dorff/Crane, p. 337. |
42 | Here, our rabbi should be made aware, however, that long-term survival is a difficult criterion in the modern age compared to the Talmudic era. This should probably not be over-emphasized, however, because it can discriminate against poor people and people of color who are more likely to have multiple and serious medical pre-conditions because of poorer previous access to quality medical care and the direct negative effects of poverty on health. (See: https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC7762908 accessed on 2 January 2023). |
43 |
References
- Bognar, Greg. 2015. “Fair Innings”. Bioethics 29: 251–61. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Dorff, Elliot N., and Jonathan K. Crane, eds. 2013. The Oxford Handbook of Jewish Ethics and Morality. New York: Oxford UP. [Google Scholar]
- Ghanayim, Khalid. 2006. Excused Necessity in Western Legal Philosophy. Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence 19: 31–65. [Google Scholar]
- Grodin, Michael A., Johnathan I. Kelly, Erin L. Miller, Robert Kirschner, and Joseph Polak. 2019. Rabbinic Responsa and Spiritual Resistance during the Holocaust: The Life-for-Life Problem. Modern Judaism 39: 296–325. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kirschner, Robert S. 1985. Rabbinic Responsa of the Holocaust Era. Translated with Introductions and Notes by Robert Kirschner. New York: Schocken Books. [Google Scholar]
- Kohler, George Y. 2018. Against the Heteronomy of Halacha–Hermann Cohen’s Implicit Rejection of Kant’s Critique of Judaism. Dinei Israel Yearbook 32: 189–209. [Google Scholar]
- Maccoby, Hyam. 2013. The Philosophy of the Talmud. London: Routledge, p. 136f. [Google Scholar]
- Newman, Louis E. 1990. Woodchoppers and Respirators: The Problem of Interpretation in Contemporary Jewish Ethics. Modern Judaism 10: 17–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Resnicoff, Steven H. 1998. Jewish Law Perspectives on Suicide and Physician-Assisted Dying. Journal of Law and Religion 13: 289–349. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Ripstein, Arthur. 2009. Force and Freedom: Kant’s Legal and Political Philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard UP. [Google Scholar]
- Rosner, Fred. 2007. Contemporary Biomedical Ethical Issues and Jewish Law. Hoboken: KTAV Publishing House, Inc. [Google Scholar]
- Solnica, Amy, Leonid Barski, and Alan Jotkowitz. 2020. Allocation of Scarce Resources during the COVID-19 Pandemic: A Jewish Ethical Perspective. Jewish Medical Ethics 46: 444–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Taylor, Charles. 2007. A Secular Age. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, pp. 157, 168–70. [Google Scholar]
- Thompson, Judith Jarvis. 1985. The Trolley Problem. The Yale Law Journal 94: 1395–415. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- White, Douglas B., and Derek C. Angus. 2020. A Proposed Lottery System to Allocate Scarce COVID-19 Medications: Promoting Fairness and Generating Knowledge. JAMA 324: 329–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Williams, Alan. 1997. Intergenerational Equity: An Exploration of the ‘fair innings’ argument. Health Economics 6: 117–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zohar, Noam. 1997. Alternatives in Jewish Bioethics. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Zoloth, Laurie. 1999. Health Care and the Ethics of Encounter—A Jewish Discussion of Social Justice. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, pp. 161–67. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Kohler, G.Y. The Talmudic Rabbi as Triage Officer: Decision-Making in Times of COVID-19. Religions 2024, 15, 344. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15030344
Kohler GY. The Talmudic Rabbi as Triage Officer: Decision-Making in Times of COVID-19. Religions. 2024; 15(3):344. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15030344
Chicago/Turabian StyleKohler, George Y. 2024. "The Talmudic Rabbi as Triage Officer: Decision-Making in Times of COVID-19" Religions 15, no. 3: 344. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15030344
APA StyleKohler, G. Y. (2024). The Talmudic Rabbi as Triage Officer: Decision-Making in Times of COVID-19. Religions, 15(3), 344. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15030344