Origen’s ‘Celsus’: Questions of Identity
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Materials and Methods
2.1. ‘Celsus’ and His Alleged Epicureanism
Celsus should be exposed as one who contradicts himself, saying the opposite. For from other writings he is revealed to be an Epicurean, yet here, because it seems more reasonable to attack the account without acknowledging the doctrines of Epicurus he pretends [to believe] that ‘there is something better in human nature than the earthly, and akin to the divine’, and he says that ‘those for whom this’, i.e., the soul, ‘is in good condition have an overriding desire for what is akin to them’, meaning god, ‘and ever yearn both to hear and to remember something about him’.(Cels 1.8.9–16, my translation)1
What did Origen actually know about the author of the work to which he replies? The verb παρειλήφαμεν (‘we gather’) implies that this is information handed down to Origen and others, not something that he is intimately familiar with. And while ‘this other one’ (on which see our footnote) might suggest to some that Origen knew that the writer was to be identified as the second of the Epicureans, there are significant doubts about both the text and whether it was intended to make this identification even if it were correct. Why should one even mention the first if one knew that the author was the second of these Epicureans? Perhaps Origen was excluding the first of them as he seemed rather early to be devoting such effort to attacking Christianity in its infancy. But again, κατὰ Ἀδριανὸν καὶ κατωτέρω (‘under Hadrian and/or more recent’) seems rather vague if Origen had been able to make a positive identification.For he knew that by acknowledging that he was an Epicurean he would fail to have credibility in his accusation against those who in whatever way introduce providence and place god at the head of reality. For we gather that there were two Epicureans called Celsus, the previous one under Nero, and this other one under Hadrian and/or more recent.(Cels 1.8.21–26)2
Why introduce a conditional clause concerning Celsus’ identity, if it had been a simple matter of agreement? It is tempting to deduce (a) from Origen’s words and (b) from the general agreement that this ‘Celsus’ had Platonist affiliations that he either does not know much at all about this ‘Celsus’, or that he was himself beginning to have understandable suspicions that he wasn’t who he first thought he was.But Plato obviously did not consider men who bequeathed such poems as ‘divinely inspired’, whereas he who is better able to judge than Plato, the Epicurean Celsus, if at least [ei ge]3 he is the one who also composed the other two books against Christians,4 when quarrelling with us, presumably called ‘divinely inspired’ those whom he did not think divinely inspired’.5
2.2. ‘Celsus’ and the Authority of Plato
2.3. Names and Shadow-Boxing: Polemics against Whom?
2.4. Origenes and His Criticism of Longinus’ Hedonism
Origenes agreed that Plato is taking care over the grace of his writing, not however because he is aiming at pleasure, but in the course of using this comparison for the presentation of what he [Socrates] felt.(Proclus In Tim. 60.1–4 [=Origenes Frg. 9])
With the other passages, this builds up a picture of a sustained debate between Longinus and Origenes over various matters raised in the earlier parts of the Timaeus, and above all about the diction employed by the author there. As Longinus did not regard Origenes as somebody who wrote more than the very occasional work, it is clear that these debates occurred in person, and, assuming that Porphyry was not himself present, then we must suppose that he heard about them from his early teacher Longinus. At any rate, Porphyry informs us, through Proclus,24 of one encounter involving Longinus and Origenes, when the latter “spent three whole days shouting and going red in the face, and getting into quite a sweat”. Such personal observations confirm the part played by oral communication here, but in this case there are no such amusing details about Longinus’ part in this inquiry, which cannot be safely reconstructed. My suspicion is that Longinus had been attending Origenes’ lectures on the early part of the Timaeus, and had been raising issues that the lecturer was finding difficult to answer.Longinus points out here too that Plato worries about the freshness and variety of his diction (ὀνομάτων), pronouncing the same things in a variety of ways. The deed he called “ancient”, the tale he called “old”, and the gentleman “not young”, yet he is making the same point throughout even when able to call everything by the same term. But he (Longinus) was ‘a lover of diction’ (φιλόλογος), as Plotinus says of him, and ‘not a lover of wisdom’ (φιλόσοφος [Porphyry, Vita 21]).22 Origenes did not agree that he [Plato] was aiming at artificial pleasure (ἡδονῆς … μεμηχανημένης) and various cosmetic embellishments, but [said] that he was concerned for a spontaneous and unembellished plausibility and accuracy in his character-portrayal, and moreover that this kind of communication comes spontaneously,23 as becomes an educated man. He thinks Aristoxenus the musical writer was right in saying that the dispositions of the philosophers extended to their voices, exhibiting an orderly quality in everything they say.
3. Results
4. Discussion
4.1. Plato and Homer
Who, after all, is more grandiloquent than Homer? Even when he brings gods into strife and battle, he does not fall short of capturing their likeness, but matches the nature of their deeds ‘in his lofty language’ (hypsêlologoumenos). This is the argument that confronts us.(In Tim. I.64.4–7 [=I.97.9–12vR])
4.2. Origen on Platonic Style
And if one should dare to say it, the beautiful and practised diction of Plato and those who spoke similarly has only been of benefit to a few, if at all, whereas that of the majority who have taught and written more economically in a practical and inexact manner [have benefitted] more. Indeed, one can only see Plato in the hands of those thought to be language-lovers (philologoi),33 whereas Epictetus is admired also by ordinary people and those inclined to receive benefit, since they are conscious of the self-improvement that comes from his words. And we are not saying this out of criticism of Plato …(Cels 6.2).34
4.3. Celsus as Longinus
5. Conclusions
- Origen’s identification of ‘Celsus’ as an Epicurean cannot have been based on secure knowledge;
- ‘Celsus’ was in fact a nom de plume of a kind quite familiar in those times;
- There is a significant parallel between Origen’s treatment of ‘Celsus’ as an Epicurean and Origenes’ complaints that Longinus’ explanation of the early pages of the Timaeus made Plato a hedonist;
- The distinction between Origen and Origenes should therefore be abandoned if chronology permits;
- Origen treats ‘Celsus’ as a poor philosopher and a philologus;
- Origen therefore suspected, at least as his detailed reading continued, that the real author of the True Logos was his former auditor Longinus, whose works Origen had indeed closely read,40 associated as he was with ‘loftiness’ both in literary theory and by name.
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Ἐλεγκτέον δὴ ὡς τὰ ἐναντία ἑαυτῷ λέγοντα τὸν Κέλσον. Εὑρίσκεται μὲν γὰρ ἐξ ἄλλων συγγραμμάτων ἐπικούρειος ὤν· ἐνταῦθα δὲ διὰ τὸ δοκεῖν εὐλογώτερον κατηγορεῖν τοῦ λόγου μὴ ὁμολογῶν τὰ Ἐπικούρου προσποιεῖται κρεῖττόν τι τοῦ γηΐνου εἶναι ἐν ἀνθρώπῳ συγγενὲς θεοῦ, καί φησιν ὅτι οἷς τοῦτο εὖ ἔχει, τουτέστιν ἡ ψυχή, πάντῃ ἐφίενται τοῦ συγγενοῦς, λέγει δὲ τοῦ θεοῦ, καὶ ἀκούειν ἀεί τι καὶ ἀναμιμνήσκεσθαι περὶ ἐκείνου ποθοῦσιν. |
2 | ᾜδει γὰρ ὅτι ὁμολογῶν ἐπικούρειος εἶναι οὐκ ἂν ἔχοι τὸ ἀξιόπιστον ἐν τῷ κατηγορεῖν τῶν ὅπως ποτὲ πρόνοιαν εἰσαγόντων καὶ θεὸν ἐφιστάντων τοῖς οὖσι. Δύο δὲ παρειλήφαμεν Κέλσους γεγονέναι ἐπικουρείους, τὸν μὲν πρότερον κατὰ Νέρωνα τοῦτον δὲ κατὰ Ἀδριανὸν καὶ κατωτέρω. I read τὸν δὲ rather than τοῦτον δὲ, as there is no other instance in the eight books of Cels of a μὲν … δὲ construction where μὲν is preceded by the article and δὲ by a form of the demonstrative οὕτος, or any demonstrative. If obliged to read τοῦτον δὲ I would interpret it as ‘the more recent one’. |
3 | Ei ge occurs eleven times in Cels, of which four belong to what Celsus says (2.17, 2.31, 3.12, 3.62), and four more occur within fifteen words of Celsus’ name (4.36, 7.55, 8.15, and 8.67). We infer that it is closely associated with polemics, challenging the opponent to accept or reject the condition. It will generally cast real doubt on the assumption being introduced, dependent on context. Celsus uses it in this way, Origen less consistently (at 6.2, 6.64, 7.26). Comparable use of eiper features as a way of conditionally (and temporarily) accepting the assumptions of opponents in the words of Celsus himself (Cels 2.18, 2.63, 6.78), and Origen often uses it similarly at 1.10, 4.35, 4.67, 4.91, 4.94, 6.57, 7.32, 7.63; it introduces other conditions not believed by Origen, e.g., at 7.18 and 8.12. |
4 | This might be a title by which the work was known, i.e., a two-book work Against the Christians. But, in that case, how can one understand ‘other’, for that is supposedly not the title of the present work? |
5 | Ἀλλὰ Πλάτων μὲν δῆλός ἐστι μὴ φρονήσας ἐνθέους γεγονέναι ἄνδρας τοὺς τοιαῦτα ποιήματα καταλελοιπότας· ὁ δὲ κρίνειν μᾶλλον Πλάτωνος δυνάμενος, ὁ ἐπικούρειος Κέλσος, εἴ γε οὗτός ἐστι καὶ ὁ κατὰ Χριστιανῶν ἄλλα δύο βιβλία συντάξας, τάχα ἡμῖν φιλονεικῶν οὓς μὴ ἐφρόνει ἐνθέους ἐνθέους ὠνόμασεν. |
6 | Epistle 2 at 6.17–19 (312E–313A); Epistle 6 at 6.8 (323D) and 6.12 (322D–E); and Epistle 7 at 6.3 and 6.6–8 (341C5–342A1); cf. generally 6.17. |
7 | See 2.60 and 7.5 on 81C–D; 7.28 and 7.21 on the true earth and the myth; 6.4 on the cock to Asclepius (118A). |
8 | These were not a source of Platonic doctrine in extant Plutarch, though by the mid-second century they are much used by Platonizing thinkers, including Apuleius, Numenius and Clement Alexandrinus. |
9 | On Longinus having used this name, see Eunapius, Vitae sophistarum 4.1.4 = Longinus Frg. 5 = Porphyry T1 (Porphyrii philosophi fragmenta, ed. Smith). |
10 | Note the attention given to Lucian’s ‘Celsus’ in Keim (1873, pp. 143–51, 275–93). |
11 | Particularly the direct quotation from book 3 at Historia ecclesiatica 6.19.5–8; after Eusebius has readily identified this person with the theologian he followed: Τῆς δὴ μοχθηρίας τῶν Ἰουδαϊκῶν γραφῶν οὐκ ἀπόστασιν, λύσιν δέ τινες εὑρεῖν προθυμηθέντες, ἐπ’ ἐξηγήσεις ἐτράποντο ἀσυγκλώστους καὶ ἀναρμόστους τοῖς γεγραμμένοις, οὐκ ἀπολογίαν μᾶλλον ὑπὲρ τῶν ὀθνείων, παραδοχὴν δὲ καὶ ἔπαινον τοῖς οἰκείοις φερούσας. αἰνίγματα γὰρ τὰ φανερῶς παρὰ Μωυσεῖ λεγόμενα εἶναι κομπάσαντες καὶ ἐπιθειάσαντες ὡς θεσπίσματα πλήρη κρυφίων μυστηρίων διά τε τοῦ τύφου τὸ κριτικὸν τῆς ψυχῆς καταγοητεύσαντες, ἐπάγουσιν ἐξηγήσεις. Ὁ δὲ τρόπος τῆς ἀτοπίας ἐξ ἀνδρός, ᾧ κἀγὼ κομιδῇ νέος ὢν ἔτι ἐντετύχηκα, σφόδρα εὐδοκιμήσαντος καὶ ἔτι δι’ ὧν καταλέλοιπεν συγγραμμάτων εὐδοκιμοῦντος παρειλήφθω, Ὠριγένους, οὗ κλέος παρὰ τοῖς διδασκάλοις τούτων τῶν λόγων μέγα διαδέδοται. [6] ἀκροατὴς γὰρ οὗτος Ἀμμωνίου τοῦ πλείστην ἐν τοῖς καθ’ ἡμᾶς χρόνοις ἐπίδοσιν ἐν φιλοσοφίᾳ ἐσχηκότος γεγονώς, εἰς μὲν τὴν τῶν λόγων ἐμπειρίαν πολλὴν παρὰ τοῦ διδασκάλου τὴν ὠφέλειαν ἐκτήσατο, εἰς δὲ τὴν ὀρθὴν τοῦ βίου προαίρεσιν τὴν ἐναντίαν ἐκείνῳ πορείαν ἐποιήσατο. [7] Ἀμμώνιος μὲν γὰρ Χριστιανὸς ἐν Χριστιανοῖς ἀνατραφεὶς τοῖς γονεῦσιν, ὅτε τοῦ φρονεῖν καὶ τῆς φιλοσοφίας ἥψατο, εὐθὺς πρὸς τὴν κατὰ νόμους πολιτείαν μετεβάλετο, Ὠριγένης δὲ Ἕλλην ἐν Ἕλλησιν παιδευθεὶς λόγοις, πρὸς τὸ βάρβαρον ἐξώκειλεν τόλμημα· ᾧ δὴ φέρων αὐτόν τε καὶ τὴν ἐν τοῖς λόγοις ἕξιν ἐκαπήλευσεν, κατὰ μὲν τὸν βίον Χριστιανῶς ζῶν καὶ παρανόμως, κατὰ δὲ τὰς περὶ τῶν πραγμάτων καὶ τοῦ θείου δόξας Ἑλληνίζων τε καὶ τὰ Ἑλλήνων τοῖς ὀθνείοις ὑποβαλλόμενος μύθοις. [8] συνῆν τε γὰρ ἀεὶ τῷ Πλάτωνι, τοῖς τε Νουμηνίου καὶ Κρονίου Ἀπολλοφάνους τε καὶ Λογγίνου καὶ Μοδεράτου Νικομάχου τε καὶ τῶν ἐν Πυθαγορείοις ἐλλογίμων ἀνδρῶν ὡμίλει συγγράμμασιν, ἐχρῆτο δὲ καὶ Χαιρήμονος τοῦ Στωϊκοῦ Κορνούτου τε ταῖς βίβλοις, παρ’ ὧν τὸν μεταληπτικὸν τῶν παρ’ Ἕλλησιν μυστηρίων γνοὺς τρόπον ταῖς Ἰουδαϊκαῖς προσῆψεν γραφαῖς. |
12 | Including singular and plural of the noun, the adjective daimonios and the adverb daimoniôs. |
13 | The distribution across the 8 books is not even, for the plural of daimôn (all cases) occurs 20 times in book 1, 11, in 2, 21 in 3, 28 in 4, 16 in 5, 8 in 6, 48 in 7, and an incredible 135 times in book 8. |
14 | It is important for chronology that this work is said to have been written ‘under Galienus’ in Vit. Plot. 3, for only thus might we need to postulate two thinkers called Origenes. It is stated that Origenes ‘wrote nothing except the syngramma On Daimones, and, under Galienus, That the King is the only Creator’. But was this really a date at which Origen (d. 254) was writing? This is almost a parenthetic addition, at some distance from the verb ‘wrote’, and in these pages Porphyry routinely dates events relevant to his own life by the years of Galienus’ reign (cf. Vit. 4 [x4], and 6), and it is likely that this is the date when the work became known to him. Perhaps it was actually published posthumously, having been found in his papers. It is entirely possible that Porphyry did not know precisely when it was written, but that, unlike Longinus, he thought it was worth mentioning, since Porphyry too had a lively interest in the King of the Second Epistle. It should be noticed that Longinus (Vita 20), while regarding On Daimones as the obvious exception to Origenes’ having written nothing, never affirms that it was the only exception. |
15 | The mention of these two works occurred in the context of explaining how the pact protecting Ammonius’ doctrines from publication was broken; see (Ramelli 2009, p. 237). |
16 | Compare also Eusebius, Praeparatio Evanglica 13.13.28–29, for whom the ‘King’ is identical with the Timaean Demiurge and consequently with God the Father in Trinitarian thought. |
17 | Fragments edited by Patillon and Brisson used here, given its wider distribution (cf. also the different numbering in Männlein-Robert edn.). Many basic facts about Longinus are included in Ramelli (2009, pp. 234–35). Longinus’ methods in fragments relating to the Timaeus are discussed in (Männlein-Robert 2006), who discusses Origenes only briefly (p. 87). |
18 | E.g., 462C7: χάριτός τινος καὶ ἡδονῆς ἀπεργασίας. |
19 | This is how Plato himself had seen the abilities of inspired poets at Phaedrus 245A5–8, but to see Plato in the same light would be to see him as a crazed plaything of a divine source of inspiration, rather than as somebody who thought out what he composed in a systematically rationalist manner. |
20 | Note I.59.12–14D = I.90.6–7vR, where Longinus writes “against certain Platonists who claim that the style of this passage is spontaneous (αὐτοφυῆ τὴν ἑρμηνείαν ταύτην) and not something provided to the philosopher from a craft”. At I.86.27–30D = I.132.1–6vR we find Origenes (Frg. 14) claiming that Plato aimed at a spontaneous persuasion (πιθανότητος … αὐτοφυοῦς), and that this kind of language occurred spontaneously (τὸ εἶδος τοῦτο τῆς ἑρμηνείας αὐτοφυῶς ἔχειν). On the vexed question of identifying Cassius Longinus with ‘Longinus’, author of On the Sublime, see Section 4.1. |
21 | There is no other reference to Epicurus or to Epicureans in Book I of In Tim., and only four later, all in Book II. |
22 | As Porphyry had noted at Vit. 14.19-20. |
23 | As at I.59.12–14D = I.91.4–7vR (Frg. 9) Origenes’ emphasis on spontaneity will remind one of Plato’s affirmations about poetic ability coming by a crazy gift of inspiration rather than by any formulaic craft at Phdr. 245A5–8. |
24 | In Tim. I.63.24–64.7D = I.96.15–97.12vR = Porph. Plat. Tim. Frg. 8 = Longinus Frg. 29 = Origenes Frg. 10. |
25 | We know from Proclus In Tim. I.76.30–77.3D (=116.14–17vR = Frg. 12) that Origenes did not take the Atlantis-story at face value, seeing it not as depicting a war between human Athenians under an ancient regime and human Atlantines, but as a war between two armies of daimones, the one presumably loyal to Athena and the other to Poseidon; yet it would require a master allegorist to take what Plato said about the mimetic tribe in general at anything other than face value. |
26 | It is this passage that is intended, but the principal line is misremembered in the light of the other. |
27 | See Ramelli (2009, p. 243), for the view that Origen held Homer in high regard; Heine, however, in a dedicated study, observes at the outset that ‘Origen’s attitude to Homer is rather mysterious’, but goes on to claim that ‘One must conclude that Origen did not, overall at least, have a negative view of Homer’ (Heine 2022, pp. 336–37). Heine does not consider ‘Origenes’ as evidence for Origen. |
28 | “But Plato obviously did not consider that the gentlemen who bequeathed us such poems had been divinely inspired; yet the one who was better able to judge than Plato, our ‘Epicurean’ Celsus, … perhaps called those he didn’t think to be inspired “inspired” (οὓς μὴ ἐφρόνει ἐνθέους ἐνθέους ὠνόμασεν) to pick a quarrel with us”. |
29 | See Porphyry, Quaestionem Homericarum ad Odysseam 9.491; megalophonônia had earlier been used in a disparaging sense, as well as a neutral one indicating simply the strength of a voice or a sound. |
30 | See Galen, De Methodo Medendi 10.12.13K; and esp. Lucian, Muscae Encomium 5: τὴν μὲν γὰρ ἀνδρίαν καὶ τὴν ἀλκὴν αὐτῆς οὐχ ἡμᾶς χρὴ λέγειν, ἀλλ’ ὃς μεγαλοφωνότατος τῶν ποιητῶν Ὅμηρος. |
31 | See In Tim. 14.12 (=21.9: ὕψος) and 20 (=21.17: ὕψωσε). I defer to the view of (Halliwell 2022, pp. x–xix), that the author of On the Sublime is unknown. |
32 | Porphyry does, however, report relevant views of Longinus alongside those of Plotinus in the newly found On Principles and on Matter (94), on which see (Arzhanov 2021). |
33 | I discuss this term below, but see also (Männlein-Robert 2001, pp. 142–46). |
34 | Καὶ εἰ χρή γε τολμήσαντα εἰπεῖν, ὀλίγους μὲν ὤνησεν, εἴ γε ὤνησεν, ἡ περικαλλὴς καὶ ἐπιτετηδευμένη Πλάτωνος καὶ τῶν παραπλησίως φρασάντων λέξις· πλείονας δὲ ἡ τῶν εὐτελέστερον ἅμα καὶ πραγματικῶς καὶ ἐστοχασμένως τῶν πολλῶν διδαξάντων καὶ γραψάντων. Ἔστι γοῦν ἰδεῖν τὸν μὲν Πλάτωνα ἐν χερσὶ τῶν δοκούντων εἶναι φιλολόγων μόνον, τὸν δὲ Ἐπίκτητον καὶ ὑπὸ τῶν τυχόντων καὶ ῥοπὴν πρὸς τὸ ὠφελεῖσθαι ἐχόντων θαυμαζόμενον, αἰσθομένων τῆς ἀπὸ τῶν λόγων αὐτοῦ βελτιώσεως. Καὶ ταῦτά γε οὐκ ἐγκαλοῦντες Πλάτωνί φαμεν …. |
35 | Proclus also employs the term at In Tim. I.14.7 and I.86.24D (=I.21.4 and I.131.18vR) of Longinus, and in his In Platonis Cratylum 32 of Plato’s ‘Hermogenes’, prompted by Plato’s Cratylus 384E1. Unlike ‘philosopher’, ‘grammarian’ or ‘sophist’, the term seems not to be used for the practitioner of a particular profession. |
36 | On the Jewish speeches within Celsus’ work, see now (Arnold 2016, pp. 341–71). |
37 | Observations at 3.12 also make it clear that many Greek philologoi admire Christianity and seek to discover more about it; this also suggests that the ‘Celsus’ himself may be a philologos. |
38 | Cf. ὁ σεμνὸς φιλόσοφος at 4.30, following Arnold 2016. |
39 | Towers five times in the Iliad according to my count, once in the Odyssey; palaces three and one respectively; mountains or peaks twice in either poem. |
40 | This emerges in the Eusebian fragment of Porphyry (Hist. eccles. 6.19.8) quoted above, n. 23; though many years Origen’s junior, Longinus had once belonged to the same intellectual circle, and was certainly old enough to have influenced what was “certainly the last of” Origen’s extant works (Heine 2022, p. 335). |
41 | Longinus mentions On Daimones (Porphyry, Vit. 20), but not in an exhaustive list; and he here only concerns himself with public works, not in letters or commentary-style works for classroom use. |
42 | See especially Diogenes Laertius, Vitae philosophorum 3.58–60. Phaedo, Menexenus and Critias were often known as On Soul, Epitaphios and Atlantikos respectively. |
43 | Diogenes, Vit. phil. 6.15–18; also in Diogenes’ catalogues 3 in Crito (2.121), 1 each in Simon (2.123), Speusippus (4.4) and Xenocrates (4.13), 3 in Aristotle (5.22–23), two in Theophrastus (5.44, 5.50), 1 each in Zeno of Citium. Chrysippus, and Epicurus. |
44 | Enn. 3.3 [29] has two alternative titles at Plot. 5 and slightly different ones at 25; 2.9 [33] Against the Gnostics is a well-known example. |
References
- Arnold, Johannes. 2016. Der Wahre Logos des Kelsos: Eine Strukturanalyse. Münster: Aschendorff. [Google Scholar]
- Arzhanov, Yuri. 2021. Porphyry, on Principles and Matter: A Syriac Version of a Lost Greek Text with an English Translation. Berlin: De Gruyter. [Google Scholar]
- Clarke, Emma, John Dillon, and Jackson Hershbell. 2003. Iamblichus: On the Mysteries. Atlanta: SBL Press. [Google Scholar]
- Halliwell, Steven. 2022. Pseudo-Longinus On the Sublime. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Heine, Ronald E. 2022. Origen and Celsus on the Allegorical Reading of Homer and Moses. In Brill’s Companion to the Reception of Homer from the Hellenistic Age to Late Antiquity. Edited by Christina P. Manolea. Leiden: Brill, pp. 335–54. [Google Scholar]
- Keim, Theodor. 1873. Celsus’ Wahres Wort. Zürich: Orell. [Google Scholar]
- Männlein-Robert, Irmgard. 2001. Longin: Philologe und Philosoph. Munich: Saur. [Google Scholar]
- Männlein-Robert, Irmgard. 2006. Die Aporien des Kritikers Longin. Zur Inszenierung der Platonexegese bei Proklos. In Proklos: Methode, Seelenlehre, Metaphysik. Edited by Matthias Perkams and Rosa Maria Piccione. Leiden: Brill, pp. 71–97. [Google Scholar]
- Ramelli, Ilaria. 2009. Origen, Patristic Philosophy, and Christian Platonism: Re-Thinking the Christianisation of Hellenism. Vigiliae Christianae 63: 217–63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Translated and Edited by Tarrant, Haroldand. 2007. Proclus: Commentary on Plato’s Timaeus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Tarrant, Harold. 2009. Living by the Cratylus: Hermeneutics and Philosophic Names in the Roman Empire. International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 3: 3–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tarrant, Harold. 2017. Plotinus, Origenes and Ammonius on the King. In Religio-Philosophical Discourses in the Mediterranean World: From Plato, through Jesus, to Late Antiquity. Edited by Anders Petersen and George van Kooten. Ancient Philosophy and Religion 1. Leiden: Brill, pp. 323–37. [Google Scholar]
- Weber, Karl-Otto. 1962. Origenes der Neuplatoniker: Versuch einer Interpretation. München: Beck. [Google Scholar]
c. Celsum | Epicur– | Platon– | Aristotel– | Stoic– | Pythagor– |
---|---|---|---|---|---|
Book 1 | 13 | 15 | 4 | 7 | 9 |
Book 2 | 3 | 8 | 4 | 0 | 5 |
Book 3 | 8 | 5 | 1 | 1 | 4 |
Book 4 | 8 | 25 | 1 | 4 | 5 |
Book 5 | 5 | 5 | 1 | 1 | 7 |
Book 6 | 3 | 56 | 0 | 3 | 1 |
Book 7 | 6 | 22 | 1 | 1 | 1 |
Book 8 | 1 | 0 | 1 | 0 | 2 |
Total | 47 | 136 | 13 | 17 | 34 |
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Tarrant, H. Origen’s ‘Celsus’: Questions of Identity. Religions 2024, 15, 715. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15060715
Tarrant H. Origen’s ‘Celsus’: Questions of Identity. Religions. 2024; 15(6):715. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15060715
Chicago/Turabian StyleTarrant, Harold. 2024. "Origen’s ‘Celsus’: Questions of Identity" Religions 15, no. 6: 715. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15060715
APA StyleTarrant, H. (2024). Origen’s ‘Celsus’: Questions of Identity. Religions, 15(6), 715. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15060715