A Note on the Reality of Incomputable Real Numbers and Its Systemic Significance
Abstract
:1. Introduction
“Mathematicians, however, freely fantasize with infinite-precision real numbers. Nevertheless within pure math the notion of a real number is extremely problematic.”
2. Computational Processes and Emergent Computation
“What I have called the Babylonian idea is to say, ‘I happen to know this, and I happen to know that, and maybe I know that; and I work everything out from there. Tomorrow I may forget that this is true, but remember that something else is true, so I can reconstruct it all again. I am never quite sure of where I am supposed to begin or where I am supposed to end. I just remember enough all the time so that as the memory fades and some of the pieces fall out I can put the thing back together again every day’”([7], p. 45).
“In physics we need the Babylonian method, and not the Euclidian or Greek method”(Ibid., p. 47).
3. Arbitrary Discretization
“Experimental physicists know how difficult accurate measurements are. No physical quantity has ever been measured with more than 15 or so digits of accuracy”[3].
The reality of IRNs lies in the representative modeling roles of some of their properties, such as their infiniteness, uniqueness, singularities, and non-computability, which represent and correspond to theoretical incomplete properties of processes such as emergence and quantum-like phenomena, whereas theoretical representation, partly differentiating from the classical representation, can be applied to model very complicated transient dynamics between phases occurring when classical and quantum aspects mix.
The research on IRNs should then not be considered an abstract exercise of mathematicians but as research in a field considered to possess properties representing and corresponding to those detectable in real, even if extreme, phenomena, such as emergence and quantum phenomena.
3.1. Equivalences and Symmetries
3.2. Discretization, Multiple Modeling, and Non-Predictability
- The infiniteness of IRNs corresponds to the theoretical incompleteness of several phenomena and processes mentioned above, such as the processes of emergence and the phenomena of continuous balance between equivalences and interchangeabilities, e.g., ergodic, and quantum.
- The non-computability of subsets of real numbers, such as irrational algebraic and transcendent, i.e., IRNs, corresponds to their non-zippability into complete analytical formulae or exhaustive single models and their combinations of complexity, such as processes of emergence, phenomena that continuously acquire, lose, and recover multiple coherences, e.g., collective behaviors.
3.3. Computability
- Nondeterministic computation when, from a given input and state, the abstract machine may jump to several different possible states;
- Hypercomputation of the so-called Ω Chaitin constant or the halting probability, consisting of a real number expressing the probability that a randomly constructed program will halt depending on the program encoding used and its length [17,53,54,55]. The importance of the Chaitin constant lies in the fact that various problems in number theory are equivalent to solving the halting problem for special programs, such as searching for counterexamples and halting if one is found. For instance, this is the case for the so-called Goldbach conjecture, which states that every even integer number greater than 2 can be always expressed as the sum of two primes [56].
- Inductive Turing machines, which perform a list of defined instructions depending on the initial states and acquire a series of successive states by applying inductive reasoning and being dependent on environment phenomenology [57].
- Quantum computers, which are based on the possibility of being in superposed states. Whereas a bit can only have two states, i.e., 0 or 1, a qubit state is a linear superposition of the basis states that is described by probability amplitudes. Multiple qubits can exhibit quantum entanglement. The Quantum Universal Turing Machine (QUTM) takes advantage of the superposition principle and the entanglement among qubits [58,59,60,61,62,63], raising the research issue of whether or not it is a Turing machine.
- Qualitative analysis, which involves determining and elaborating qualitative properties of a phenomenon in a way that allows the identification or exclusion of subsequently acquired properties, such as convergence, that deal with numerical sequences, analytic properties of a function without calculating it, and pattern and multiple dynamic coherence recognition. We believe this is a very promising field of research and one that can be used to introduce new, unimaginable approaches.
- The infiniteness of IRNs corresponds to the necessary but unpredictable collapse of any equivalence, reaching arbitrary points of difference at suitable levels of description, e.g., the quantum description level;
- The incomputability of IRNs corresponds to the non-zippability of complexity into a single analytical formula or exhaustive single model [69].
4. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Maietti, M.E.; Sambin, G. Toward a minimalist foundation for constructive mathematics. In From Sets and Types to Topology and Analysis. Towards Practicable Foundations for Constructive Mathematics; Crosilla, L., Schuster, P., Eds.; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 2005; pp. 91–114. [Google Scholar]
- Kawai, T.; Sambin, G. The principle of point free continuity. Log. Methods Comput. Sci. 2019, 15, 22:1–22:25. [Google Scholar]
- Chaitin, G. How real are real numbers? Int. J. Bifurc. Chaos 2006, 16, 1841–1848. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Paperin, G.; Green, D.G.; Sadedin, S. Dual-phase evolution in complex adaptive systems. Interface 2011, 8, 609–629. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Batterman, R. Emergence, singularities, and symmetry breaking. Found. Phys. 2011, 41, 1031–1050. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Minati, G. Phenomenological structural dynamics of emergence: An overview of how emergence emerges. In The Systemic Turn in Human and Natural Sciences. A Rock in the Pond; Ulivi, L.U., Ed.; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2019; pp. 1–39. [Google Scholar]
- Feynmann, R. The Character of Physical Law; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1967. [Google Scholar]
- Licata, I.; Minati, G. Emergence, Computation and the Freedom Degree Loss Information Principle in Complex Systems. Found. Sci. 2016, 21, 863–881. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Younger, A.S.; Redd, E.; Siegelmann, H. Development of Physical Super-Turing Analog Hardware. In Unconventional Computation and Natural Computation; Ibarra, O., Kari, L., Kopecki, S., Eds.; Lecture Notes in Computer Science; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2014; Volume 8553, pp. 379–392. [Google Scholar]
- Aggarwal, C.C. Neural Networks and Deep Learning: A Textbook; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Goodfellow, I.; Bengio, Y.; Courville, A.; Bach, F. Deep Learning; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Kelleher, J.D. Deep Learning; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Shields, M.W.; Casey, M.C. A theoretical framework for multiple neural network systems. Neurocomputing 2008, 71, 1462–1476. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Bianchi, F.M.; Maiorino, E.; Kampffmeyer, M.C.; Rizzi, A.; Jenssen, R. Recurrent Neural Networks for Short-Term Load Forecasting: An Overview and Comparative Analysis; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Faloutsos, C.; Megalooikonomoum, V. On data mining, compression, and Kolmogorov complexity. Data Min. Knowl. Discov. 2007, 15, 3–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Li, M.; Vitányi, P.M.B. An Introduction to Kolmogorov Complexity and Its Applications; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Chaitin, G.J. How Much Information Can There be in a Real Number? Int. J. Bifurc. Chaos 2007, 17, 1933–1935. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Javanmardi, E.; Liu, S.; Xie, N. Exploring the Philosophical Paradigm of Grey Systems Theory as a Postmodern Theory. Found. Sci. 2020, 25, 905–925. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Liu, S.; Yang, Y. A brief introduction to grey systems theory. Grey Syst. Theory Appl. 2012, 2, 89–104. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Longo, G. Interfaces of Incompleteness. In Systemics of Incompleteness and Quasi-Systems; Minati, G., Abram, M.R., Pessa, E., Eds.; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2019; pp. 3–55. [Google Scholar]
- Longo, G. Reflections on concrete incompleteness. Philos. Math. 2011, 19, 255–280. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Minati, G. Knowledge to Manage the Knowledge Society: The Concept of Theoretical Incompleteness. Systems 2016, 4, 26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Minati, G.; Pessa, E. Collective Beings; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Minati, G.; Pessa, E. From Collective Beings to Quasi-Systems; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Minati, G.; Licata, I. Emergence as Mesoscopic Coherence. Systems 2013, 1, 50–65. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Minati, G. Big Data: From Forecasting to Mesoscopic Understanding. Meta-Profiling as Complex. Systems. Systems 2019, 7, 8. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Cruchtfield, J.P. The calculi of emergence: Computation, dynamics and induction. Physica D 1994, 75, 11–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pessa, E. Emergence, self-organization, and quantum theory. In Proceedings of the First Italian Conference on Systemics; Minati, G., Ed.; Apogeo Scientifica: Milano, Italy, 1998; pp. 59–79. [Google Scholar]
- Anderson, P.W. Can broken symmetry occur in driven systems? In Equilibrium and Nonequilibrium Statistical Mechanics; Nicolis, G., Dewel, G., Turner, P., Eds.; Wiley: New York, NY, USA, 1981; pp. 289–297. [Google Scholar]
- Anderson, P.W.; Stein, D.L. Broken symmetry, emergent properties, dissipative structures, life. Are they related? In Self Organizing Systems: The Emergence of Order; Yates, F.E., Ed.; Plenum Press: New York, NY, USA, 1985; pp. 445–457. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, B. Uncertainty Theory; Springer: Berlin, Germany, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Zhou, Z.-H. Ensemble Methods: Foundations and Algorithms; CRC Press: Boca Raton, FL, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Maynard-Smith, J. Evolution and the Theory of Games; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Weibull, J.W. Evolutionary Game Theory; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Minati, G.; Penna, M.P.; Pessa, E. Thermodynamic and Logical Openness in General Systems. Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. 1998, 15, 131–145. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- De Finetti, B. Theory of Probability; Wiley: New York, NY, USA, 1974. [Google Scholar]
- Calude, C.S. Information and Randomness; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- McAllister, J.W. Algorithmic randomness in empirical data. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 2003, 34, 633–646. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chaitin, G. Information, Randomness, and Incompleteness; Word Scientific: Singapore, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Kolmogorov, A.N. Three Approaches to the Quantitative Definition of Information. Probl. Inf. Transm. 1965, 1, 3–11. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zadeh, L.A.; Klir, G.J.; Yuan, B. (Eds.) Fuzzy Sets, Fuzzy Logic, and Fuzzy Systems: Selected Papers by Lotfi A. Zadeh; World Scientific: Singapore, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Wolfram, S. The principle of computational equivalence. In A New Kind of Science; Wolfram Media: Champaign, IL, USA, 2002; pp. 5–6. [Google Scholar]
- Siegelmann, H.T. Computation beyond the Turing Limit. Science 1995, 268, 545–548. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Copeland, B.J.; Sylvan, R. Beyond the Universal Turing Machine. Australas. J. Philos. 1999, 77, 46–67. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Copeland, B.J.; Posy, C.J.; Shagrir, O. Computability: Turing, Gödel, Church, and Beyond; MIT: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Siegelmann, H.T. Neural and super-Turing computing. Minds Mach. 2003, 13, 103–114. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cabessa, J.; Villa, A.E.P. The super-Turing computational power of interactive evolving recurrent neural networks. In ICANN 2013; Mladenov, V., Koprinkova-Hristova, P., Palm, G., Villa, A.E.P., Appollini, B., Kasabov, N., Eds.; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2013; Volume 8131, pp. 58–65, Lecture Notes in Computer Science (LNCS). [Google Scholar]
- Hogarth, M.L. Non-Turing Computers and Non-Turing Computability. In Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association (PSA); Hull, D., Forbes, M., Burian, R.M., Eds.; Philosophy of Science Association: Chicago, IL, USA, 1994; Volume 1, pp. 126–138. [Google Scholar]
- Shagrir, O.; Pitowsky, I. Physical Hypercomputation and the Church–Turing Thesis. Minds Mach. 2003, 13, 87–101. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cotogno, P. Hypercomputation and the Physical Church-Turing Thesis. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2003, 54, 181–223. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Syropoulos, A. Hypercomputation: Computing Beyond the Church-Turing Barrier; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Inoue, K.; Ito, A.; Takanami, I. On 1-inkdot alternating Turing machines with small space. Theor. Comput. Sci. 1994, 127, 171–179. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Martin, J. Introduction to Languages and the Theory of Computation; McGraw-Hill: New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Chaitin, G.J. A theory of program size formally identical to information theory. J. Assoc. Comput. Mach. 1975, 22, 329–340. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chaitin, G.J. Meta Math! The Quest for Omega; Pantheon Books: New York, NY, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Y. The Goldbach Conjecture; Word Scientific: Singapore, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Burgin, M. Superrecursive Algorithms; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Calude, C.S.; Dinneen, M.J.; Svozil, K. Reflections on quantum computing. Complexity 2000, 6, 35–37. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Deutsch, D. Quantum Theory, the Church-Turing Principle and the Universal Quantum Computer. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. Ser. A Math. Phys. Sci. 1985, 400, 96–117. [Google Scholar]
- Deutsch, D. Quantum computational networks. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. Ser. A Math. Phys. Sci. 1989, 425, 73–90. [Google Scholar]
- Deutsch, D. The Beginning of Infinity: Explanations That Transform the World; Penguin: London, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Deutsch, D.; Jozsa, R. Rapid solution of problems by quantum computation. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. Ser. A Math. Phys. Sci. 1992, 439, 553–558. [Google Scholar]
- Rosenblum, B.; Kuttner, F.; Penrose, R. Quantum Physics of Consciousness; Cosmology Science Publishers: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Siegelmann, H.T. Neural Networks and Analog Computation: Beyond the Turing Limit; Birkhäuser: Basel, Switzerland, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Ulmann, B. Analog and hybrid computer programming. In De Gruyter Textbook; De Gruyter Oldenbourg: Oldenbourg, Germany, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Mac Lennan, B.J. Natural computation and non-Turing models of computation. Theor. Comput. Sci. 2004, 317, 115–145. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brabazon, A.; O’Neill, M.; McGarraghy, S. Natural Computing Algorithms; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Nural, M.; Cotterell, M.E.; Miller, J. Using semantics in predictive big data analytics. In Proceedings of the 2015 IEEE International Congress on Big Data, Big Data Congress, Santa Clara, CA, USA, 29 October–1 November 2015; pp. 254–261. [Google Scholar]
- Cooper, B. The incomputable reality. Nature 2012, 482, 465. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Blasone, M.; Jizba, P.; Vitiello, G. Quantum Field Theory and its Macroscopic Manifestations; Imperial College Press: London, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Giuliani, A.; Zbilut, J. The Latent Order of Complexity; NovaScience: New York, NY, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Zizzi, P.A. Emergence of Universe from a Quantum Network. In Physics of Emergence and Organization; Licata, I., Sakaji, A., Eds.; World Scientific: Singapore, 2008; pp. 313–325. [Google Scholar]
Computable (availability of an algorithm that computes in finite time and with arbitrary precision) Real Numbers | Incomputable (unavailability of an algorithm that computes in finite time and with arbitrary precision) Real Numbers (IRNs) |
Generic cases include rational non-periodic, limited, algebraic decimal numbers, whereas specific cases include perfect roots. | Include algebraic, irrational, trigonometric (based on Euler’s formula), transcendent numbers, some points of convergence, and some special numbers, such as the Chaitin omega number. |
Effective Computability | Incomputability | Emergent Computation |
---|---|---|
We differentiate between symbolic computational processes and their effective computability. In the last case, the step-by-step computation process is formally available and is Turing-computable, i.e., it ends always and in a finite amount of time. | We differentiate between symbolic computational processes and their non-effective computability. In the last case, although the step-by-step computation process is formally available, it is not Turing-computable; for instance, it does not end in a limited amount of time. In such a case, we do not use results. Rather, it is possible to use approximations or computational symbolic representations for possible groupings and simplifications, such as numbers with exponents and numerical fractions, simplifications that are impossible when using approximate values that are indeed only calculated at the end. | The computation cannot be analytically completely represented, and acquired properties cannot be anticipated by considering the formal computation process.The computational processing is non-explicit, not analytically represented, and called sub-symbolic, even if the program being performed is an explicit, computable algorithm, such as ANN. Systemically, properties are acquired during ongoing networked computations. |
The role of equivalence in maintaining coherence in collective systems |
Within collective systems of interacting elements, equivalence is intended to be a reason for their unpredictable microscopic behavior, incomplete representations, and regardless of the source stability, the robustness of the collective behavior, which can be represented in different though equivalent ways. |
Equivalence relates to the interchangeability of roles assumed by interacting elements. There are countless (non-equivalent) ways of maintaining the same equivalent level of coherence even after going through temporary local incoherencies that are recovered in a number of ways. |
For instance, there are several variable correlations among temporary, local, and different non-equivalently correlated communities, e.g., groups of people that make up the nightlife, rather than only establishing the same long-range correlation, e.g., flocks. |
A model represents a system that is logically closed when |
(a) There is an almost complete formal, explicit (symbolic, not sub-symbolic) description of the relations between the state variables of the model available. |
(b) There is an almost complete and explicit, i.e., analytically describable, description of the interaction between the system and its environment available. |
(c) The knowledge of values related to the previous two points allows the deduction of all (assumed to be finite and limited numbers) possible states and properties that the system can take together with its structural characteristics. |
A system is classified as logically open when there is a violation of at least one of the three points above. Logical openness is a specification of the theoretical incompleteness. |
Turing computability |
A function is said to be Turing-computable if all the function’s values can be computed with a Turing machine. |
We may specify such generic definition. |
Formally, a Turing machine is specified as a quadruple T = (Q, Σ, s, δ) where |
|
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2021 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Minati, G. A Note on the Reality of Incomputable Real Numbers and Its Systemic Significance. Systems 2021, 9, 44. https://doi.org/10.3390/systems9020044
Minati G. A Note on the Reality of Incomputable Real Numbers and Its Systemic Significance. Systems. 2021; 9(2):44. https://doi.org/10.3390/systems9020044
Chicago/Turabian StyleMinati, Gianfranco. 2021. "A Note on the Reality of Incomputable Real Numbers and Its Systemic Significance" Systems 9, no. 2: 44. https://doi.org/10.3390/systems9020044
APA StyleMinati, G. (2021). A Note on the Reality of Incomputable Real Numbers and Its Systemic Significance. Systems, 9(2), 44. https://doi.org/10.3390/systems9020044