Next Article in Journal
Dust Formation in the Wind of AGB Stars—The Effects of Mass, Metallicity and Gas-Dust Drift
Previous Article in Journal
Effective Actions for Regge Piecewise Flat Quantum Gravity
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Communication

Causality in a Qubit-Based Implementation of a Quantum Switch

Departamento de Física Teórica, Universidad Autónoma de Madrid, 28049 Madrid, Spain
Universe 2022, 8(5), 269; https://doi.org/10.3390/universe8050269
Submission received: 28 March 2022 / Revised: 29 April 2022 / Accepted: 4 May 2022 / Published: 4 May 2022
(This article belongs to the Section Foundations of Quantum Mechanics and Quantum Gravity)

Abstract

:
We introduce a qubit-based version of the quantum switch, consisting of a variation of the Fermi problem. Two qubits start in a superposition state in which one qubit is excited and the other is in the ground state. However, it is not defined which is the excited qubit. Then, after some time, if a photon is detected, we know that it must have experienced an emission by one atom and then an absorption and re-emission by the other one, but the ordering of the emission events by both qubits is undefined. While it is tempting to refer to this scenario as one with indefinite causality or a superposition of causal orders, we show that there is still a precise notion of causality: the probability of excitation of each atom is totally independent of the other one when the times are short enough to prevent photon exchange.

1. Introduction

The notion of causality in quantum physics seems to have experienced a revisitation during the last few years due to new theoretical and experimental results revolving around the “quantum switch” [1,2,3,4,5,6,7,8,9]. A quantum switch is an interferometric setup where the optical path of a photon depends on the state of a control qubit. If the qubit is in state zero, the photon will follow a path which includes undergoing two linear-optical operations A and B, while if the state is one, the path includes the operations in the opposite order: first B and then A. Now, if the control qubit is in a superposition state of zero and one, then the path is undefined, and so is the order of the operations A and B. This is typically referred to as “indefinite causal order” or “superposition of causal orders”. However, it has been noted [10] that a more accurate phrasing would be that the order is entangled with the external control qubit. Tracing out the qubit, the system is left in a classical mixture of probabilities rather than in a superposition, which seems to be impossible to obtain without the aid of the external system. It should also be noted that the quantum switch does not violate “causal inequalities” [11], and therefore invoking a non-classical causal order is not necessary to explain the results. This seems to be a general result within standard quantum mechanics [12].
Relativistic causality and Lorentz invariance are the cornerstones of quantum field theory [13,14]. Quantum mechanics is a low-energy, fixed-number approximation of quantum field theory. Although not explicitly relativistic by construction, quantum mechanics respects the basic principle of causality, being a non-signaling theory where superluminal propagation of physical magnitudes is forbidden [15,16]. A paradigmatic example of causality at the quantum level is the so-called Fermi problem [17]. At t = 0 , a two-level neutral atom A is in its excited state and a two-level neutral atom B in its ground state, with no photons present. The atoms do not interact directly, but can emit and absorb photons—and therefore exchange them. If they are separated by a distance r, the total probabilities for each atom of being in a given state are completely independent of the other atom at times t < r / c , c being the speed of light [18,19,20,21], and therefore it is impossible to extract any information at superluminal rates out of this system.
In this work, we propose a modification of this model which transforms the Fermi problem into a qubit-based version of the quantum switch. The atoms are connected to a beam splitter, through which we inject a single photon. Then, we still have one atom excited and the other in the ground state, but it is undefined whether the excited atom is A or B. The atoms can emit and exchange photons. Under these conditions, if after some time a photon is detected, we do not know whether the atom has been emitted by A, absorbed by B and then re-emitted, or first emitted by B, then absorbed by A and re-emitted. Therefore, the ordering of the emission events is undefined and we have an analogue of the quantum switch. Note that A and B play the role of the local laboratories of Alice and Bob, which perform the quantum switch superoperation by exchanging the photon. The detected photon would play the role of the control qubit in the standard quantum switch. However, we will show that there is a precise notion of causality in this setup: the probabilities of excitation of the atoms do not depend on the other atom when they are outside the light cone of the other.

2. Model and Results

For simplicity, we focus on a 1D setup with two qubits, A and B , interacting with a quantum bosonic field. The qubits are defined by two states |e〉 and |g〉 with energy gap Ω ( = 1 ). They interact locally with a one-dimensional field, E ( x ) ,
E ( x ) = i d k N ω k e i k x a k + H . c . .
This field would be a a 1D version of the electric field, mimicking the standard “d times E” coupling in quantum optics. As usual, it is defined by a continuum of Fock operators [ a k , a k ] = δ k k , and ω k = c | k | , where c is the speed of light. N is a normalization constant which would depend on the particular setup.
We consider the standard Hamiltonian, H = H 0 + H I , with the free part
H 0 = 1 2 Ω ( σ A z + σ B z ) + k ω k a k a k ,
and the interaction between them
H I = d A σ A x E ( x A ) + d B σ B x E ( x B ) .
Here, x A and x B are the fixed positions of the atoms, and d A , d B are dipole moments.
The atoms do not interact directly, but they can emit and absorb photons, and therefore they can also exchange them. If the initial state contains a definite excited atom and the other is in the ground state—for instance, the state is | e A g B 0 —we have the classic Fermi model formulation (Figure 1a,b). In this 1D setup, it can be shown [21] that the system behaves causally, meaning that the probability of excitation of atom B is independent of atom A for t < r / c , r = x B x A being the distance between the qubits. Note that this probability can be different from zero for t < r / c , but this is not a causality problem as long as it is not dependent on qubit A and therefore cannot be used to transmit information. The probability of excitation of the initially unexcited qubit only becomes sensitive to the other qubit for t > r / c .
Now, let us consider that the atoms are connected to a 50–50 beam-splitter through which a single photon is injected. Then, if the qubits start in the ground state, after absorbing a photon, they are initialized in the state:
| ψ = 1 2 ( | e A g B 0 + | g A e B 0 ) ,
in which one atom is excited, although we do not know whether it is atom A or B, and no photons are present (Figure 1c). Then, after a sufficiently long time, if a photon is detected we know that it has been emitted by one atom, absorbed by the other and re-emitted. However, it is undefined whether it was first emitted by A, absorbed by B and re-emitted, or first emitted by B, absorbed by A and re-emitted. In this sense, we have built up a variant of the quantum switch: there are two events in the past of the photon—the two photo-emissions—whose temporal ordering is completely undefined. The detection of the photon plays the role of the quantum degree of freedom in the quantum switch: if photons are ignored, the qubit system would be in a statistical mixture of both possibilities, not a truly quantum superposition. If the time is not long enough to completely rule out the possibility of just a single emission, the source of the detected photon would still be indistinguishable, and this would merely add new terms to the superposition without changing the conclusions below.
The aim of this work is to show that despite this indefiniteness in the temporal ordering, sometimes referred to as indefinite causality or superposition of causal orders, there is a well-defined notion of causality in this system. To this end, we are interested in the dynamics of the probability of excitation P e A , P e B of atoms A and B. In the Heisenberg picture, they would be given by:
P e i = ψ | P i e ( t ) | ψ
where P i e ( t ) is the projector over the excited state of atom i
P i e = | e i e i | = σ i + σ i
in the Heisenberg picture. The Heisenberg equations are
P ˙ i e ( t ) = i [ P i e ( t ) , H ] = d i σ i y ( t ) E ( x i , t ) ,
which give rise to
P e i ( t ) P e i ( 0 ) = d i 0 t d t σ i y ( t ) E ( x i , t ) .
In this case, we state that the initial probabilities of excitation are
P e A ( 0 ) = P e B ( 0 ) = 1 / 2 .
Therefore, putting together Equations (5) and (8), we state that the probabilities of excitation would be given by:
P e i = 1 2 d i 0 t d t ψ | σ i y ( t ) E ( x i , t ) | ψ .
Let us now analyze E ( x i , t ) . We start with the Heisenberg equations of the operators a k and a k :
a k ˙ ( t ) = i [ a k ( t ) , H ] = i ω k a k ( t ) N ω k i d i e i k x i σ i x ( t ) a k ˙ ( t ) = i [ a k ( t ) , H ] = i ω k a k ( t ) N ω k i d i e i k x i σ i x ( t ) .
Integrating these equations, we get:
a k ( t ) = e i ω k t a k ( 0 ) N ω k e i ω k t i d i e i k x i 0 t d t σ i x ( t ) e i ω k t a k ( t ) = e i ω k t a k ( 0 ) N ω k e i ω k t i d i e i k x i 0 t d t σ i x ( t ) e i ω k t .
Now, inserting them in Equation (1), the total field evaluated at x in the Heisenberg picture is decomposed
E ( x , t ) = E 0 ( x , t ) + E A ( x , t ) + E B ( x , t )
into the homogenous part of the field
E 0 ( x , t ) = i d k N ω k e i ( k x ω t ) a k + H . c .
and the back action of A and B onto the field
E i ( x , t ) = i d i N × × 0 t σ i x ( t ) ω k e i k ( x x i ) i ω k ( t t ) d k d t + H . c .
We now have to evaluate the field both in x A and x B . Let us start with x A . Clearly, the field is decomposed into three parts:
E ( x A , t ) = E 0 ( x A , t ) + E A ( x A , t ) + E B ( x A , t ) .
Naturally, E 0 ( x A , t ) cannot depend on atom B in any way. We should focus on E B ( x A , t ) which carries an explicit dependence on atom B. We have:
E B ( x A , t ) = i d B N × 0 t σ B x ( t ) ω k e i k ( x A x B ) i ω k ( t t ) d k d t + H . c . = d B N × d d t 0 t σ B x ( t ) e i k r i ω k ( t t ) d k d t + H . c .
Considering that ω k = c | k | , we state that the first integral is:
e i k r i ω k ( t t ) d k + H . c . = 0 e i k ( r + c ( t t ) ) d k + 0 e i k ( r c ( t t ) ) d k + 0 e i k ( r + c ( t t ) ) d k + 0 e i k ( r c ( t t ) ) d k .
Performing the change of variables k = k in the second and third integrals, this can be rearranged as:
e i k r i ω k ( t t ) d k + H . c . = e i k ( r + c ( t t ) ) d k + e i k ( r c ( t t ) ) d k .
The first integral is zero, since t cannot be larger than t, by construction, while the second gives rise to a Dirac delta:
e i k ( r c ( t t ) ) d k = 2 π δ ( c t ( c t r ) ) = 2 π c δ t ( t r c ) .
Plugging this result in Equation (17), we finally conclude that the B-dependent part of the field evaluated at x A is:
E B ( x A , t ) = 2 π d B N c d d t σ B x ( t r c ) θ t r c ,
where the Heavyside step function makes explicit the fact that E B ( x A , t ) is 0 for t < r / c . We now turn to the A-dependent part of the field at x A , which from Equation (15), and following the same techniques as before, leads to:
E A ( x A , t ) = 2 π d A N c d d t σ A x ( t ) .
This can be different from zero for t > 0 . However, since σ A x conmutes with the interaction hamiltonian, the commutator
[ H , σ A x ] = i Ω σ A y
does not involve atom B (see Equation (24) below), and neither do the commutators [ H , [ H , σ A x ] ] , [ H , [ H , [ H , σ A x ] ] ] , etc. Therefore, the time-dependent operator σ A x ( t ) cannot be dependent on atom B in any way.
Putting everything together, we have shown that the time-dependent field evaluated at x A , E ( x A , t ) is not dependent on atom B for t < r / c . There are B-independent parts that can be different from zero at any time, but the B-dependent parts are only non-zero for t > r / c . Recalling Equation (10), we see that we still have to analyze the behavior of σ A y ( t ) . Again, the commutator
[ H , σ A y ] = i Ω σ A x + 2 i d A σ A z E ( x A )
does not contain any observable relation with atom B, and the same holds for all the commutators involved in the dynamics of σ A y .
Therefore, we conclude that the probability of excitation of atom A P e A is completely independent of atom B for t < r / c . From Equation (10), we see that there will be three different terms P e A 0 , P e A A and P e A B related to E 0 , E A and E B respectively. The first two can be different from zero at any time t > 0 , but are completely independent of atom B. The last one is only non-vanishing for t > r / c .
In order to get more specific results, we can plug our exact results from Equations (21) and (22) into Equation (10) and retain only the leading terms in the commutator expansion of σ A y ( t ) and σ A x ( t ) . Recalling Equations (23) and (24), we have:
σ A y ( t ) = σ A y + O ( Ω t ) σ B x t r c = σ B x Ω t r c σ B y + O ( Ω t ) 2 .
Then, up to order d 2 and Ω t , we have:
P e A B = 2 π d A d B N Ω c r c t d t ψ | σ A y σ B y | ψ = 2 π d A d B N Ω c ( t r c ) θ t r c P e A A = 2 π d A 2 N Ω c 0 t d t ψ | σ A y σ A y | ψ = 2 π d A 2 N Ω t c .
Interestingly, the first term only appears due to the fact that we are considering an initial superposition | ψ , since it comes from
ψ | σ A y σ B y | ψ = 1 ,
which would be zero if we replace | ψ with | e A g B 0 or | g A e B 0 , as in the original Fermi problem. Thus, our modification of the Fermi setup in order to build a quantum switch does change the excitation probabilities of the atoms, but does not change the fact that they behave causally.
While all the analysis above refers to atom A, it also holds for atom B. Again, using Equations (13)–(15) to evaluate the field at x B , we find that the A-dependent part of the field at x B is:
E A ( x B , t ) = i d A N × 0 t σ A x ( t ) ω k e i k ( x B x A ) i ω k ( t t ) d k d t + H . c . ,
and it is straightforward to see that all the analysis above follows along the same lines. Therefore, we have shown that the probabilities of excitation of both atoms are insensitive to the presence of the other atom until they enter the light cone of the other, as required by relativistic causality. These results apply in principle to any setup with two qubits interacting with a 1D bosonic quantum field—e.g., a superconducting-circuit setup such as in [21]—and could presumably be extended to 3D setups using similar Fermi-problem techniques [19,20].

3. Summary and Conclusions

In summary, we have illustrated the relation between two notions that could seem to be in contradiction at first sight: on the one hand, the strong principle of causality underlying quantum theory, and on the other hand, the recent developments around quantum switch devices, which seem to challenge causality with concepts such as superposition of causal orders or indefinite causality. To this end, we have revisited a paradigmatic model of causality at the quantum level—the two-atom Fermi problem—and modified it in order to introduce a new version of the standard interferometric quantum switch, where the temporal ordering of two events—in this case, two photo-emissions by the atoms—is not defined. We show that despite this indefiniteness in the ordering, the basic principle of causality survives, since the probabilities of excitation of both atoms behave in a causal way, as in the original Fermi problem. This suggests the necessity of careful distinctions [10,22,23] between temporal ordering—which can be quantum-controlled and therefore indefinite—and causal order, which is always well defined in standard quantum setups such as experimental quantum switches [4,5,6,7,8,9]. While modifications or extensions of quantum theory could lead to new causal structures that could be relevant in quantum gravity [2,24,25], standard quantum mechanics does possess an standard causal structure.

Funding

C.S. received financial support through the Ramón y Cajal programme (RYC2019-028014-I).

Conflicts of Interest

The author declares no conflict of interest. The funders had no role in the design of the study; in the collection, analyses, or interpretation of data; in the writing of the manuscript, or in the decision to publish the results.

References

  1. Oreshkov, O.; Costa, F.; Brukner, C. Quantum correlations with no causal order. Nat. Commun. 2012, 3, 1092. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  2. Brukner, C. Quantum causality. Nat. Phys. 2014, 10, 259. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  3. Chiribella, G.; D’Ariano, G.M.; Perinotti, P.; Valiron, B. Quantum computations without definite causal structure. Phys. Rev. A 2013, 88, 022318. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  4. Procopio, L.; Moqanaki, A.; Araújo, M.; Costa, F.; Calafell, I.A.; Dowd, E.G.; Hamel, D.R.; Rozema, L.A.; Brukner, C.; Walther, P. Experimental superposition of orders of quantum gates. Nat. Commun. 2015, 6, 8913. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  5. Rubino, G.; Rozema, L.A.; Feix, A.; Araujo, M.; Zeuner, J.M.; Procopio, L.M.; Brukner, C.; Walther, P. Experimental verification of an indefinite causal order. Sci. Adv. 2017, 3, e1602589. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  6. Goswami, K.; Giarmatzi, C.; Kewming, M.; Costa, F.; Branciard, C.; Romero, J.; White, A.G. Indefinite Causal Order in a Quantum Switch. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2018, 121, 090503. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  7. Goswami, K.; Romero, J. Experiments on quantum causality. AVS Quantum Sci. 2020, 2, 037101. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  8. Goswami, K.; Cao, Y.; Paz-Silva, G.A.; Romero, J.; White, A.G. Increasing communication capacity via superposition of order. Phys. Rev. Res. 2020, 2, 033292. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Guo, Y.; Hu, X.-M.; Hou, Z.-B.; Cao, H.; Cui, J.-M.; Liu, B.-H.; Huang, Y.-F.; Li, C.-F.; Guo, G.-C.; Chiribella, G. Experimental Transmission of Quantum Information Using a Superposition of Causal Orders. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2020, 124, 030502. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  10. Costa, F. A no-go theorem for superpositions of causal orders. Quantum 2022, 6, 663. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  11. Branciard, C.; Araujo, M.; Feix, A.; Costa, F.; Brukner, C. The simplest causal inequalities and their violation. New J. Phys. 2015, 18, 013008. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  12. Purves, T.; Short, A.J. Quantum Theory Cannot Violate a Causal Inequality. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2021, 127, 110402. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  13. Weinberg, S. The Quantum Theory of Fields; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1995. [Google Scholar]
  14. Eberhard, P.H.; Ross, R.R. Quantum field theory cannot provide faster-than-light communication. Found. Phys. Lett. 1989, 2, 127. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  15. Ghirardi, G.C.; Rimini, A.; Weber, T. A General Argument against Superluminal Transmission through the Quantum Mechanical Measurement Process. Lett. Nuovo Cimento 1980, 27, 293. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  16. Peres, A. Classical interventions in quantum systems. II. Relativistic invariance. Phys. Rev. A 2000, 61, 022117. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  17. Fermi, E. Quantum theory of radiation. Rev. Mod. Phys. 1932, 4, 87. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  18. Buchholz, D.; Yngvason, J. There are no Causality Problems for Fermi’s Two-Atom System. Phys. Rev. Lett. 1994, 73, 613. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  19. Milonni, P.W.; James, D.F.V.; Fearn, H. Photodetection and causality in quantum optics. Phys. Rev. A 1995, 52, 1525. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  20. Power, E.A.; Thirunamachandran, T. Analysis of the causal behavior in energy transfer between atoms. Phys. Rev. A 1997, 56, 3395. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  21. Sabín, C.; del Rey, M.; García-Ripoll, J.J.; Leon, J. Fermi Problem with Artificial Atoms in Circuit QED. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2011, 107, 150402. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  22. MacLean, J.-W.; Reid, K.; Spekkens, R.W.; Resch, K.J. Quantum-coherent mixtures of causal relations. Nat. Commun. 2017, 8, 15149. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  23. Paunkovic, N.; Vojinovic, M. Causal orders, quantum circuits and spacetime: Distinguishing between definite and superposed causal orders. Quantum 2020, 4, 275. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  24. Zych, M.; Costa, F.; Pikovski, I.; Brukner, C. Bell’s theorem for temporal order. Nat. Commun. 2019, 10, 3772. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  25. Moller, N.S.; Sahdo, B.; Yokomizo, N. Quantum switch in the gravity of Earth. Phys. Rev. A 2021, 104, 042414. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Figure 1. (a) Qubit A is initially in the excited state, while qubit B is initially in the ground state. A photon is emitted by qubit A and absorbed by qubit B, which then emits a photon and goes back to the ground state. (b) Qubit B is initially in the excited state, while qubit A is initially in the ground state. Qubit B emits a photon which is absorbed by qubit A and then qubit A emits a photon and relaxes back to the ground state. (c) The initial state is a superposition of the initial states in scenarios (a,b). Therefore, we know that a photon must be emitted, absorbed and re-emitted, but the ordering of the emissions is not defined.
Figure 1. (a) Qubit A is initially in the excited state, while qubit B is initially in the ground state. A photon is emitted by qubit A and absorbed by qubit B, which then emits a photon and goes back to the ground state. (b) Qubit B is initially in the excited state, while qubit A is initially in the ground state. Qubit B emits a photon which is absorbed by qubit A and then qubit A emits a photon and relaxes back to the ground state. (c) The initial state is a superposition of the initial states in scenarios (a,b). Therefore, we know that a photon must be emitted, absorbed and re-emitted, but the ordering of the emissions is not defined.
Universe 08 00269 g001
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Sabín, C. Causality in a Qubit-Based Implementation of a Quantum Switch. Universe 2022, 8, 269. https://doi.org/10.3390/universe8050269

AMA Style

Sabín C. Causality in a Qubit-Based Implementation of a Quantum Switch. Universe. 2022; 8(5):269. https://doi.org/10.3390/universe8050269

Chicago/Turabian Style

Sabín, Carlos. 2022. "Causality in a Qubit-Based Implementation of a Quantum Switch" Universe 8, no. 5: 269. https://doi.org/10.3390/universe8050269

APA Style

Sabín, C. (2022). Causality in a Qubit-Based Implementation of a Quantum Switch. Universe, 8(5), 269. https://doi.org/10.3390/universe8050269

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop