1. Introduction
The notion of causality in quantum physics seems to have experienced a revisitation during the last few years due to new theoretical and experimental results revolving around the “quantum switch” [
1,
2,
3,
4,
5,
6,
7,
8,
9]. A quantum switch is an interferometric setup where the optical path of a photon depends on the state of a control qubit. If the qubit is in state zero, the photon will follow a path which includes undergoing two linear-optical operations A and B, while if the state is one, the path includes the operations in the opposite order: first B and then A. Now, if the control qubit is in a superposition state of zero and one, then the path is undefined, and so is the order of the operations A and B. This is typically referred to as “indefinite causal order” or “superposition of causal orders”. However, it has been noted [
10] that a more accurate phrasing would be that the order is entangled with the external control qubit. Tracing out the qubit, the system is left in a classical mixture of probabilities rather than in a superposition, which seems to be impossible to obtain without the aid of the external system. It should also be noted that the quantum switch does not violate “causal inequalities” [
11], and therefore invoking a non-classical causal order is not necessary to explain the results. This seems to be a general result within standard quantum mechanics [
12].
Relativistic causality and Lorentz invariance are the cornerstones of quantum field theory [
13,
14]. Quantum mechanics is a low-energy, fixed-number approximation of quantum field theory. Although not explicitly relativistic by construction, quantum mechanics respects the basic principle of causality, being a non-signaling theory where superluminal propagation of physical magnitudes is forbidden [
15,
16]. A paradigmatic example of causality at the quantum level is the so-called Fermi problem [
17]. At
, a two-level neutral atom
A is in its excited state and a two-level neutral atom
B in its ground state, with no photons present. The atoms do not interact directly, but can emit and absorb photons—and therefore exchange them. If they are separated by a distance
r, the total probabilities for each atom of being in a given state are completely independent of the other atom at times
,
c being the speed of light [
18,
19,
20,
21], and therefore it is impossible to extract any information at superluminal rates out of this system.
In this work, we propose a modification of this model which transforms the Fermi problem into a qubit-based version of the quantum switch. The atoms are connected to a beam splitter, through which we inject a single photon. Then, we still have one atom excited and the other in the ground state, but it is undefined whether the excited atom is A or B. The atoms can emit and exchange photons. Under these conditions, if after some time a photon is detected, we do not know whether the atom has been emitted by A, absorbed by B and then re-emitted, or first emitted by B, then absorbed by A and re-emitted. Therefore, the ordering of the emission events is undefined and we have an analogue of the quantum switch. Note that A and B play the role of the local laboratories of Alice and Bob, which perform the quantum switch superoperation by exchanging the photon. The detected photon would play the role of the control qubit in the standard quantum switch. However, we will show that there is a precise notion of causality in this setup: the probabilities of excitation of the atoms do not depend on the other atom when they are outside the light cone of the other.
2. Model and Results
For simplicity, we focus on a 1D setup with two qubits,
A and
, interacting with a quantum bosonic field. The qubits are defined by two states |
e〉 and |
g〉 with energy gap
(
). They interact locally with a one-dimensional field,
This field would be a a 1D version of the electric field, mimicking the standard “d times E” coupling in quantum optics. As usual, it is defined by a continuum of Fock operators and , where c is the speed of light. N is a normalization constant which would depend on the particular setup.
We consider the standard Hamiltonian,
with the free part
and the interaction between them
Here, and are the fixed positions of the atoms, and , are dipole moments.
The atoms do not interact directly, but they can emit and absorb photons, and therefore they can also exchange them. If the initial state contains a definite excited atom and the other is in the ground state—for instance, the state is
—we have the classic Fermi model formulation (
Figure 1a,b). In this 1D setup, it can be shown [
21] that the system behaves causally, meaning that the probability of excitation of atom B is independent of atom A for
,
being the distance between the qubits. Note that this probability can be different from zero for
, but this is not a causality problem as long as it is not dependent on qubit A and therefore cannot be used to transmit information. The probability of excitation of the initially unexcited qubit only becomes sensitive to the other qubit for
.
Now, let us consider that the atoms are connected to a 50–50 beam-splitter through which a single photon is injected. Then, if the qubits start in the ground state, after absorbing a photon, they are initialized in the state:
in which one atom is excited, although we do not know whether it is atom A or B, and no photons are present (
Figure 1c). Then, after a sufficiently long time, if a photon is detected we know that it has been emitted by one atom, absorbed by the other and re-emitted. However, it is undefined whether it was first emitted by A, absorbed by B and re-emitted, or first emitted by B, absorbed by A and re-emitted. In this sense, we have built up a variant of the quantum switch: there are two events in the past of the photon—the two photo-emissions—whose temporal ordering is completely undefined. The detection of the photon plays the role of the quantum degree of freedom in the quantum switch: if photons are ignored, the qubit system would be in a statistical mixture of both possibilities, not a truly quantum superposition. If the time is not long enough to completely rule out the possibility of just a single emission, the source of the detected photon would still be indistinguishable, and this would merely add new terms to the superposition without changing the conclusions below.
The aim of this work is to show that despite this indefiniteness in the temporal ordering, sometimes referred to as indefinite causality or superposition of causal orders, there is a well-defined notion of causality in this system. To this end, we are interested in the dynamics of the probability of excitation
,
of atoms A and B. In the Heisenberg picture, they would be given by:
where
is the projector over the excited state of atom
i
in the Heisenberg picture. The Heisenberg equations are
which give rise to
In this case, we state that the initial probabilities of excitation are
Therefore, putting together Equations (
5) and (
8), we state that the probabilities of excitation would be given by:
Let us now analyze
. We start with the Heisenberg equations of the operators
and
:
Integrating these equations, we get:
Now, inserting them in Equation (
1), the total field evaluated at
x in the Heisenberg picture is decomposed
into the homogenous part of the field
and the back action of
A and
B onto the field
We now have to evaluate the field both in
and
. Let us start with
. Clearly, the field is decomposed into three parts:
Naturally,
cannot depend on atom B in any way. We should focus on
which carries an explicit dependence on atom B. We have:
Considering that
, we state that the first integral is:
Performing the change of variables
in the second and third integrals, this can be rearranged as:
The first integral is zero, since
cannot be larger than
t, by construction, while the second gives rise to a Dirac delta:
Plugging this result in Equation (
17), we finally conclude that the B-dependent part of the field evaluated at
is:
where the Heavyside step function makes explicit the fact that
is 0 for
. We now turn to the A-dependent part of the field at
, which from Equation (
15), and following the same techniques as before, leads to:
This can be different from zero for
. However, since
conmutes with the interaction hamiltonian, the commutator
does not involve atom B (see Equation (
24) below), and neither do the commutators
,
, etc. Therefore, the time-dependent operator
cannot be dependent on atom B in any way.
Putting everything together, we have shown that the time-dependent field evaluated at
,
is not dependent on atom B for
. There are B-independent parts that can be different from zero at any time, but the B-dependent parts are only non-zero for
. Recalling Equation (
10), we see that we still have to analyze the behavior of
. Again, the commutator
does not contain any observable relation with atom B, and the same holds for all the commutators involved in the dynamics of
.
Therefore, we conclude that the probability of excitation of atom A
is completely independent of atom B for
. From Equation (
10), we see that there will be three different terms
,
and
related to
,
and
respectively. The first two can be different from zero at any time
, but are completely independent of atom B. The last one is only non-vanishing for
.
In order to get more specific results, we can plug our exact results from Equations (
21) and (
22) into Equation (
10) and retain only the leading terms in the commutator expansion of
and
. Recalling Equations (
23) and (
24), we have:
Then, up to order
and
, we have:
Interestingly, the first term only appears due to the fact that we are considering an initial superposition
, since it comes from
which would be zero if we replace
with
or
, as in the original Fermi problem. Thus, our modification of the Fermi setup in order to build a quantum switch does change the excitation probabilities of the atoms, but does not change the fact that they behave causally.
While all the analysis above refers to atom A, it also holds for atom B. Again, using Equations (
13)–(
15) to evaluate the field at
, we find that the A-dependent part of the field at
is:
and it is straightforward to see that all the analysis above follows along the same lines. Therefore, we have shown that the probabilities of excitation of both atoms are insensitive to the presence of the other atom until they enter the light cone of the other, as required by relativistic causality. These results apply in principle to any setup with two qubits interacting with a 1D bosonic quantum field—e.g., a superconducting-circuit setup such as in [
21]—and could presumably be extended to 3D setups using similar Fermi-problem techniques [
19,
20].