1. Introduction
An
injective Banach lattice is an injective object in the category of Banach lattices with positive contractions as morphisms. Arendt [
1] (Theorem 2.2) proved that the injective objects are the same if we take the regular operators with contractive modulus as morphisms. The first example of an injective Banach lattice was provided by Abramovich who did not use the term in [
2]:
A Dedekind complete -space with unit is an injective Banach lattice. Later Lotz rediscovered this fact in [
3] where the concept of injective Banach lattice was introduced. Lotz also proved that
each -space is an injective Banach lattice; see [
3] (Proposition 3.2). Hence, injective Banach lattices differ essentially from injective Banach spaces. Indeed,
, the Banach lattice of real-valued continuous functions on an extremally disconnected Hausdorff compact space
K is the only injective object (up to isomorphism) in the category of Banach spaces and linear contractions (see the Nachbin–Goodner–Kelley–Hasumi Theorem [
4] (Theorem 6)). The important contribution to the study of injective Banach lattices belongs to Cartwright [
5] who found the
order intersection property and proved that a Banach lattice
X is injective if and only if
X has the order intersection property and there exists a contractive positive projection to
X in
(the property
); see [
6] (Definition 5.10.9 (3), Theorems 5.10.10, and 5.10.11). Another significant advance is due to Haydon [
7]. He discovered that an injective Banach space has a mixed
-
-structure and proved three theorems on the representation of injective Banach lattices as the space of order continuous operators between Dedekind complete Banach lattices with strong order units [
7] (Theorems 5C), the space of integrable functions with respect to a Stone-algebra-valued modular measure [
7] (Theorems 6H), and the space of all continuous sections of a continuous bundle of
-spaces [
7] (Theorems 7B).
The
Boolean valued approach to the theory of injective Banach lattices was initiated in [
8,
9]. By the main result announced in [
8] (Theorem 1) and proved in [
9] (Theorem 4.4), each theorem about
-spaces within Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory has its counterpart for injective Banach lattices. Translation of theorems from
-spaces to injective Banach lattices is carried out by the machinery of Boolean valued analysis; see [
6] (§ 5.10 –5.13). For other contributions of the Boolean valued approach to injective Banach lattices see [
6,
10,
11] and for other aspects of injective Banach lattices see [
12,
13,
14,
15].
The present article is a continuation of the paper [
11] which deals with the geometric characterization of Banach spaces whose duals are injective Banach lattices. The article is organized as follows:
Section 2 collects some Boolean valued requisites that include the Boolean valued interpretation of Banach spaces, Banach lattices, and
-spaces.
Section 3 yields the necessary and sufficient conditions for the unit ball in a Banach space be such that the space will admit some partial ordering that make the space an injective Banach lattice.
Section 4 characterizes injective Banach lattices among ordered Banach spaces by Boolean valued interpretation of the result by Ellis that an ordered Banach space is an
-space if and only if it is regular, enjoys the Riesz decomposition property, and its norm is additive on the positive cone.
Section 5 contains an isomorphic characterization of injective Banach lattices by interpreting in an appropriate Boolean valued model the Timofte result that a directed, monotone complete ordered normed space
X with the Riesz decomposition property is order and topologically isomorphic to some
-space if and only if the positive cone of
X is generated by some bounded closed convex subset not containing the zero. We start
Section 6 with a description of the dual space, and then give a dual characterization of an injective Banach lattice.
For the theory of Banach lattices and positive operators we refer to the books [
16,
17,
18]. The prerequisites of the theory of Boolean valued models are briefly presented in [
19] (Chapter 9) and [
6] (Chapter 1); see also [
20,
21,
22] for more detail.
Throughout the sequel, and stand for the closed unit balls of a normed space X and its topological dual . Let denote the positive cone of an ordered vector space X, and we will assume that is closed. Also, stands for the Boolean algebra of band projections of a vector lattice X. We let: designate the assignment by definition, while and will symbolize the naturals and the reals.
2. Some Boolean Valued Requisites
The main purpose of this section is to provide notation and terminology as well as some results about Boolean valued representation we will need in what follows.
Throughout the sequel
is a complete Boolean algebra with unit
and zero
, while
stands for the corresponding
Boolean valued universe. There is a natural way of assigning to each formula
of
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with choice,
in short, the
Boolean truth value with
. We say that the statement
is true within
and write
if
. There is a smooth mathematical technique for revealing interplay between the interpretations of one and the same fact in the two models, the
von Neumann universe and the
Boolean valued universe . The relevant
ascending-and-descending machinery rests on the functors of
canonical embedding and
ascent , acting from
into
, and of
descent , acting from
into
, see [
6,
21] for details. The operations of descent, ascent, and canonical embedding can be naturally extended to mappings and relations, so that they are applicable to algebraic structures. So, there arise some functors of Boolean valued analysis whose interplay is of import in applications; see [
21] (Chapter 3).
The basic properties of a Boolean valued universe are formulated in the three principles: The transfer principle tells us that all theorems of ZFC are true within . The maximum principle asserts that if , then there exists such that . A partition of unity in is a family such that and whenever . The mixing of a family in by a partition of unity in is an element satisfying for all . The mixing principle states that in there exists a mixing of every family by each partition of unity. Thus, the maximum principle guarantees the existence of various Boolean valued “replicas” or “counterparts” of usual mathematical objects, while the mixing principle shows how these replicas may be constructed.
The following property of descents turns out rather useful in interpreting mathematical objects and statements in the Boolean valued universe
; see [
21] (2.3.8). Given
, denote by
the set of all mixings of all families in
X by arbitrary partitions of unity in
. If
and
, then for an arbitrary subset
with
and all formulas
and
of ZFC we have
Applying the transfer and maximum principles to the
-theorem on the existence of the reals, find
called the
reals within which satisfies
. The
Gordon Theorem [
23] states that the descent
of
(with the descended operations and order) is a universally complete vector lattice. Moreover, there is a Boolean isomorphism
from
onto
such that
for all
and
; see [
21] (Theorem 5.2.2) and [
6] (Theorem 2.2.4). Moreover, the universally complete vector lattice
endowed with the descended multiplications is a semiprime
f-algebra with ring unity
. Moreover, for every
the band projection
acts as the multiplication by the
; see [
6] (Theorem 2.3.2). For a special
, the Gordon Theorem was first discovered by Takeuti; see [
24,
25].
The
bounded descent of
is the order ideal in
generated by
and equipped with the order-unit norm
:
Write
, since
is uniquely defined by
. Clearly,
is a Dedekind complete
-space with unit
. By the Kreĭns–Kakutani Representation Theorem
with
K an extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff space, the Stone space of
.
Let
be a Banach space within
and
. Define the mapping
from
to
as the descent
of the norm
. Then
(with the descended operations) is a vector space,
is an
-valued norm on
, and
is a Banach–Kantorovich space; see [
11] (Definition 2.7). (Not to be confused with the concept of
Kantorovich-Banach space or
-
space in short, which is, by definition, a Banach lattice with an order continuous Levi norm. These properties appear in the literature under different names; see Definition 7 and the footnote on page 89 in [
26]). The
bounded descent of
is defined as the set
equipped with the descended operations with the
mixed norm, i.e.,
for all
; see [
11] (Definition 2.6).
Observe that
is a Dedekind complete
f-algebra with ring and order unit
. Moreover, both
and
admit the structure of
-module; see [
6] (5.8.5, 5.8.7).
A
projection P on a Banach space
X is an idempotent in
, the Banach algebra of bounded linear operators on
X, that is,
and
. When speaking of a
Boolean algebra of projections in a Banach space
X we always mean some set
of commuting norm one projections on
X which is a Boolean algebra under the operations
and in which the zero and the identity operators in
X serve as the top and bottom of
.
A projection
on a Banach space
X is an
L-
projection if
for all
, and
is an
M-
projection if
for all
. The
L-projections and
M-projections different from the zero and the identity are referred to as
nontrivial. The sets of all
L-projections and
M-projections on
X are denoted by
and
. Furthermore,
is a complete Boolean algebra,
is a (generally not complete) Boolean algebra, and the mapping
is a Boolean isomorphism from
onto
(see [
11] (Theorem 2.10)) and from
into
.
Let
be a Boolean algebra of norm one projections in a Banach space
X. Take
, a family
in X, and a partition of the unit
in
. If
for all
, then we say that
x is a
mixing of
by
; cf. (2) in
Section 2 A subset
is
-
complete or
-
complete if, given a family
in
C and a partition of unity
in
, we have
. A Banach space
X is
-complete or
-
cyclic if
, the mixing of a family is unique whenever it exists, and the closed unit ball
of
X is
-complete.
The Boolean valued representation of Banach spaces is described as follows (see [
19] (Theorems 8.3.1 and 8.3.2) or [
11] (Theorem 5.8.11)): Recall that a linear operator
is
-linear if
for all
; here
X and
Y are Banach spaces with Boolean algebras of projections and the latter are identified with
. A one-to-one
-linear operator is a
-
isomorphism. An isometric
-
isomorphism of Banach spaces is a
-isometry, and a
-isometric lattice homomorphism between Banach lattices is a
lattice -isometry.
(1) The bounded descent of a Banach space without nontrivial M-projections within is a Banach space with the -complete unit ball and isomorphic to . Conversely, if X is a Banach space whose unit ball is -complete with , then there exists a Banach space without nontrivial M-projections within whose M-descent is linearly -isometric to X and is unique up to linear isometry.
As regards an alternative approach to Boolean valued interpretation of Banach space theory with very important applications to the module structure of von Neumann algebras see [
27] and the references therein. We proceed with the result of [
9] (Theorem 3.1) about the Boolean valued representation of Banach lattices. To this end, put
.
(2) The bounded descent of a Banach lattice from is a -cyclic Banach lattice. Conversely, if X is a -cyclic Banach lattice, then in there exists a Banach lattice unique up to lattice isometry whose bounded descent is lattice -isometric to X. Moreover, if and only if there is no M-projection in other than 0 and .
Recall the conventional definition of an injective Banach lattice. A real Banach lattice
X is
injective if, for every Banach lattice
Y, every closed vector sublattice
, and every positive linear operator
there is a positive linear extension
of
with
. The transfer principle for injective Banach lattices reads as follows (see [
9] (Theorem 4.4) and [
6] (Theorem 5.12.5)):
A bounded descent of an -space from is an injective Banach lattice with . Conversely, if X is an injective Banach lattice and , then there is an -space within whose bounded descent is lattice -isometric to X.
Among the useful consequences of this fact we have the following representation result: An operator
enjoys the
Levy property if
and each increasing net
in
X has the supremum
provided that the net
is order bounded in
. Given an injective Banach lattice
with
, there is a
strictly positive Maharam operator (i.e., an interval preserving order continuous linear operator such that
implies
) enjoying the Levi property and satisfying
for all
; see [
9] (Corollary 4.5). In this event we say that
X is
representable as .
3. Banach Space Characterization
In this section we will present the necessary and sufficient conditions on the unit ball of a Banach space X for X to admit a partial ordering making X into an injective Banach lattice. We start with recalling a similar characterization of -spaces.
Definition 1. A subset is Λ-convex if for all and with . A nonempty Λ-convex subset F of a Λ-convex set C is a Λ-face of C if whenever and with and , , it follows that and . In the case when , we speak of convex sets and faces. The cone C is minihedral whenever the intersection of every two translates of C is a translate of C; i.e., for all there is satisfying .
We also define the -convex hull of a set as the intersection of all -convex sets in X including A and put . Observe that if for some -convex F and D then .
Theorem 1. Let X be a Banach space. Then X is linearly isometric to an -space if and only if there is a maximal face such that and the cone is minihedral.
Proof. See [
4] (§ 18, Theorem 1). □
Lemma 1. Let X be a -complete Banach space and C a -complete convex subset of X. Then an arbitrary maximal Λ-face of X is -complete.
Proof. Assume that F is a maximal -face of C and denote by the subset of C consisting of all mixtures of families in F by partitions of unity in . It suffices to prove that . Consider determined by a partition of unity in and a family in F; i.e., for all . Suppose that for some and with . Fix and put and where . Then and hence and . It follows that , whence for each fixed , so that as is a partition of unity. Similarly, . Thus is a -face of C; and, as and F is a maximal -face of C, we conclude that and F is a -face of C. □
Let be a Banach space within and let be a -complete Banach space with the norm , where is the descent of the internal norm and .
Lemma 2. Let and be convex sets in and let stand for the internal unit sphere of ; i.e., . Then
.
.
.
if and only if .
is a maximal Λ-face of if and only if is a maximal face of .
Proof. : It suffices to observe that for if and only if and if and only if .
: By definition, means that . Because is the descent of , the latter is equivalent to the equality which occurs if and only if for all .
: Note that
if and only if
within
. By the maximum principle this is equivalent to the existence of
,
, and
such that
. Thus,
means that
for some
,
, and
with
.
: A similar argument applies.
: The claim
is a maximal face of
means that
Calculating the Boolean truth values for the universal quantifiers by formula (1), we arrive at the equivalent statement: For all , , and the relation implies . Considering that and are equipped with the descended operations and by definition, we see that the latter can be rephrased as and implies that and . □
Theorem 2. For a real Banach space X with the following are equivalent:
(1) X is linearly -isometric to an injective Banach lattice Y with .
(2) We have
- (a)
is a complete Boolean algebra and the unit ball of X is -complete;
- (b)
the subset S of the unit sphere of X consisting of all such that for all includes a maximal face for which ;
- (c)
is a minihedral cone.
Proof. : If 2(1) holds, then in 2(2) is also true and, by Theorem 1, there exists an -space within such that is linearly -isometric to Y. There is no loss of generality in assuming . Let stand for the unit sphere of . By the transfer principle, Theorem 1 is true within and the maximum principle yields the existence of with is a maximal face of with and the cone is minihedral. Note that and are straightforward from Lemma 2.
: Assume that are fulfilled. Then X is -isomeric to . Put , , and . According to statements , and of Lemma 2, is the unit sphere of and is a maximal face of , since by Lemma 1. Similarly, and in view of assertions and of Lemma 2. Moreover, is a minihedral cone in if and only if so is in X, since and for all . The transfer principle enables us to apply Theorem 1 within and conclude that is isometric to some -space within . It follows that X is -isometric to and is an injective Banach lattice. □
Remark 1. In Theorem 2, we can replace with and define the cone C as the closure of , where designates the closed convex hull of A, while stands for the collection of all with , , , and a finite partition of unity in .
4. Ordered Banach Space Characterization
In this section, we consider the question of when an ordered normed space is an injective Banach lattice. First, we introduce some definitions.
Definition 2. An ordered Banach space X is -complete or -cyclic whenever X is a -complete Banach space, consists of positive projections, and is - complete; see definitions in Section 3. Lemma 3. For an ordered Banach space X to be -complete it is necessary and sufficient that X be -isometric and order isomorphic to the descent of some ordered Banach space within .
Proof. The Banach part follows from
Section 2. The rest of the claim is justified in the same way as in [
9] (Theorem 3.1). □
Definition 3. An ordered normed space X is regular (or has a Riesz norm) if X enjoys the properties:
(1) is absolute monotone; i.e., if and then .
(2) if , , and ; then there is with , and .
Lemma 4. Let be an ordered Banach space within and . The following hold:
(1) X has the Riesz decomposition property if and only if has the Riesz decomposition property.
(2) X is regular if and only if is regular.
Proof. The first claim is immediate from the definitions. Regularity of
means that the following formulas are true within
:
The appearance of
in the last formula is justified since in Definition 3(2) we can replaced
by a dense subset of
. Using the descent rule (1)
and
, we see that
and
if and only if
and
. Therefore, the regularity of
is equivalent to
To ensure that the last two conditions are equivalent to the regularity of
we only have to observe that
if and only if
and
if and only if
for all
as well as to use the equations
for all
and
. The only matter that needs clarification is as follows: If condition (1) in Definition 3 is satisfied, then
implies
. Indeed, if
, then there exist a nonzero projection
and a real
such that
, whence
. So we get that
while
, which contradicts 3(1). □
Denote by
and
the set of all countable partitions of unity in
and the collection of all finite subsets of
X. Let
X be a
-cyclic Banach lattice. Recall that
, where
is a Banach–Kantorovich space with
-valued norm
. Denote
In this section we will construct the injective sum of injective Banach lattices and characterize the injective Banach lattices in terms of summable sequences.
Lemma 5. Let X be a -complete ordered Banach space. Then
(1)
given a finite collection , we have(2)
given a family in X such that o-summable is o-summable, we haveMoreover, is o-summable if and only if the left hand-side in (4) is finite.
Proof. (1):
Considering finite collection
and an arbitrary countable partition of unity
in
, we deduce
Hence, the inequality ≤ holds. To prove the reverse inequality, take an arbitrary
and choose a countable partition of unity
such that
Forming sums over
and taking the supremum over
in (5), we obtain
Since
is arbitrary, we arrive at the required equality.
(2): According to 5(1), for every
we can write
It follows that the family
is order summable if and only if the numerical family
is bounded, since
is Dedekind complete. Taking the supremum in (6) over all finite subsets
and using the fact that
is a Fatou norm we arrive at (4). □
Lemma 6. Let be an ordered Banach space within and let be the restricted descent of . If , then for the following are equivalent:
within ;
.
.
Proof. The equivalence
can be easily deduced by using some simple properties of descents and ascents [
6] (1.5.5(1), 1.5.6, 1.6.4, and 1.6.6), while
immediate from Lemma 5. □
Definition 4. Let X be a -complete normed ordered vector space. Say that the norm is -additive on if for every we have and is -generating if for every there exist with and .
Lemma 7. Let X be a -complete Banach space ordered by a -complete positive cone and let consist of positive projections. Then
the norm is -additive on if and only if for all ;
the cone is -generating if and only if for every there exist with and .
Proof. The claims are immediate from Lemma 6 and Definition 4. □
Theorem 3. For an ordered Banach space X and a complete Boolean algebra the following are equivalent:
X is an injective Banach lattice with .
The next four conditions hold:
- (a)
X has the Riesz decomposition property.
- (b)
X is regular.
- (c)
and the unit ball and the positive cone are -complete.
- (d)
The norm of X is -additive.
Proof. An ordered Banach space
X is
-complete if one of the items 3(1) and
holds. Thus, we can assume that
for some ordered Banach space
within
. By 2.8
X is an injective Banach lattice if and only if
is
-space. By the Ellis result [
28] (Corollary 9.23)
is an
-space if and only if
is regular and has the Riesz decomposition property while the norm
is additive on
. Thus, we have to show only that
has the above properties if and only if
X enjoys
. The latter, however, follows from Lemmas 4 and 7. □
Remark 2. Another way of characterizing injective Banach lattices is to use the properties of positive generation and additivity on the positive cone. An ordered Banach space is an injective Banach lattice with if and only if the following hold: exists in for all ; the unit ball and the positive cone are -complete; X is -generated; X is -additive. This fact can be obtained as a Boolean valued interpretation of [29] (Chap 2, Theorem 6.2). 5. Isomorphic Characterization
In this section we give the conditions for a monotone complete normed ordered vector space to be topologically and order isomorphic to some injective Banach lattice.
Definition 5. A normed ordered vector space X is monotone complete, if every monotone Cauchy sequence in X is convergent. Say that is monotone norm -complete if, given an increasing sequence in X with order convergent to zero in Λ, there exists such that is order convergent to zero in Λ. In the same way we define monotone -completeness, by considering relatively uniform convergence instead of order convergence.
Monotone complete ordered normed spaces arise in several different areas. Some recent advances can be found in [
30].
Lemma 8. Let be a normed ordered vector space and . Then X is monotone σ-complete if and only if is monotone σ-complete.
Proof. By Lemma 3, there is a
-valued norm
on
X such that
is a Banach–Kantorovich space and
for all
; see 2.5. Using the interplay between convergent sequences in
and
(see [
19] (Propositions 8.1.4(3, 4) or [
6] (Propositions 2.4.5 and 2.4.6)), we can prove that
is monotone complete
if and only if
is monotone norm
-complete. Arguing as in [
19] (Theorem 7.1.2), we can also prove that
is monotone complete if and only if
is norm
-complete. Consequently, we only have to show that the monotone
-completeness of
is equivalent to the monotone norm
-completeness of
. This can be done by the same reasoning as in the proof of [
19] (Theorem 2.2.3). To sketch the proof, denote by
the set of all mappings
such that
is a partition of unity in
and define the order relation on
by letting
whenever
implies
for all
. Given an increasing Cauchy sequence
and
, put
. Then
is an increasing net. Let
be a decreasing sequence in
such that
and
for all
. For an arbitrary
there exist a partition of unity
in
with
for all
. Now, if
and
, then
. If
X is norm
r-complete, there is
with
and, clearly,
. □
The main result of this section will be obtained as a Boolean valued interpretation of the following two statements. Recall that X is referred to as directed or generating if .
Lemma 9. Assume that an normed ordered vector space X is directed, monotone complete and has the Riesz decomposition property. Then X is order isomorphic to some -space if and only if the positive cone can be written as for some closed bounded convex set .
Proof. This is a special case of Timofte’s isomorphic characterization of
-spaces among Hausdorff topological ordered vector space; see [
31] (Theorem 14). □
Lemma 10. If X and B are the same as in Lemma 9, then there is an equivalent -norm on X such that the following hold:
(1) for all and with .
(2) If there exists such that and then for all and with .
Proof. By hypotheses there is an equivalent
-norm
on
X such that
for all
, where
; see [
31] (Lemma 2 and Theorem 9). This yields 10(1). As in the proof of [
31] (Lemma 2), we can verify that
for all
, where
is the Minkowski functional of
. Now, 10(2) is immediate from the definition of the Minkowski functional. □
Lemma 11. Let be a Banach space within and . If is -complete and , then is closed and convex if and only if B is closed and convex. If B is bounded then is bounded.
Proof. Observe that is a limit point of if and only if for every there exist a partition of unity in and a family in B such that and , that is, x is a limit point of . Together with Lemma 1, this yields the first claim. The second claim is obvious. □
Positive operators are often automatically continuous:
Every positive operator from a Banach lattice to a normed vector lattice is continuous; see [
16] (Corollary 4.4) and [
18] (Proposition 1.3.5)). Below we need a stronger version of this fact.
Lemma 12. Let X and Y be two ordered Banach spaces whose positive cones are closed. If X is directed then every positive operator from X to Y is continuous.
Proof. See [
26] (Corollary 6), where the authorship of the statement is attributed to Lozanovsky. □
Theorem 4. Let be a complete Boolean algebra and . Assume that a -complete normed ordered vector space X is regular and monotone complete. Also, X has the Riesz decomposition property. Then the following are equivalent:
There exists an equivalent norm on X such that is an injective Banach lattice with .
There exists a bounded, closed, and convex -complete set such that and .
Proof. : Assume . Then is representable as with a strictly positive order continuous operator having the Levy property. If then evidently B is convex. Moreover, B is closed and bounded, since the formula implies that is continuous and for all . If for some and then so that . Given , a partition of unity in and a family such that for all , we have and hence . Finally, check that each can be written as with and . Assume first that is an order unit in . Then there exists such that and we can pick a disjoint sequence in with . Since and has the Levy property, exists in and . Thus, and . To settle the general case, denote by the band projection onto the band generated by , pick with , and put , . Then is an order unit in and, by the above, for some . It follows that as desired.
: Let
be a Boolean valued representation of
X. Identify
with
and put
. Arguing as in the proof of [
9] (Theorem 3.1), we can show that
is an normed ordered vector space within
, and
as
is
-complete. Moreover,
is regular and has the Riesz decomposition property by Lemma 4 and
is monotone complete by Lemma 8. Assume 4(2)and put
. Then
is bounded, closed, and convex by Lemma 11. If
then
so that
and
. To see that
, we need only to check that
for all
or, which is the same,
. But even more is true:
by hypothesis. Thus,
meets the requirements of Lemma 9. By the transfer principle, Lemma 9 is true within
and so
there is an equivalent
-norm
on
. In particular,
is Dedekind complete vector lattice
by [
31] (Proposition 8). Let
and
stand for the descents of
and
.
Prove that . Interpreting Lemma 10(1) in yields that for all and with . For an arbitrary there is a countable partition of unity in such that for all n. Then and, by hypothesis, for some and . Put and . Observe that , while exists in . If , then as and . Moreover, . Thus, so that implies , i.e., .
To demonstrate the converse inclusion note that we can pick
such that
and
as
B is closed and convex and
. Note also that
consists of all elements of the form
with
,
, and
. Hence,
. It follows that within
we have
and
, where
stands for the unit ball of
. By the transfer principle, Lemma 10 is applicable within
so that
for all
and
with
. Descending, we get that
for all
and
with
. By hypothesis, for an arbitrary
there are
and
such that
and
. Observe that
is invertible in
and we deduce
Thus, and the inclusion follows. To complete the proof, we need only note that is a Banach lattice with (see 2.8) and apply Lemma 12. □
A rather different isomorphic characterization of
-spaces is given by the following result due to Schlotterbeck:
A Banach lattice X is lattice isomorphic to an -space if and only if every positive summable sequence in X is absolutely summable; see [
32] (Theorem 2.7).
Definition 6. Put . A sequence in X is -summable if there is such that for every there exists a partition of unity in with for all and . In this event x is called the -sum of . If the sequence is positive and the norm in X is absolute monotone, then we see that that for every there exists a countable partition of unity in with for all with . A sequence is absolutely -summable if Taking
to be the two-element Boolean algebra
in Definition 6, we arrive at the definition of a
summable and an
absolute summable sequence; see [
32] (page 240).
Theorem 5. For a -cyclic Banach lattice X the following are equivalent:
(1) There is a countable partition of unity in such that is lattice -isomorphic to an injective Banach lattice for every .
(2) Every positive -summable sequence in X is absolutely -summable.
Proof. Let
X be a
-cyclic Banach lattice and let
be a Banach lattice within
, the Boolean valued representation of
X; see 2.7(1). By Lemma 5(2) a sequence
in
X is absolutely
-summable if and only if
exists in
. But the latter is means that
the sequence
is absolutely summable in
. It is easy that
-sum of
exists and equals
x if and only if
with
if and only if
Consequently, 5(2) means that
every positive summable sequence in
is absolutely summable
. The transfer principle enables us to apply within
the Schlotterbeck characterization of
-spaces, so that by the maximum principle there exists
such that
is an
-space
and
is a lattice isomorphism of
onto
. Assume, moreover, that
for some
. Then
is a lattice
-isomorphism of
onto
and
. To settle the general case, observe that the sentence
is true, so that by the transfer principle
It follows that there is a partition of unity
in
such that
. Put
,
,
, and
. Note that
is a lattice isomorphism from
onto
”. It follows that
is a lattice
-isomorphism from
onto
and
. □
Remark 3. Condition 5(1) admits the equivalent formulation: There are a Banach lattice and a countable partition of unity in such that (a) is an order dense ideal of X; (b) is an injective Banach lattice; (c) for all ; and (d) and are lattice -isometric under the induced norms. To demonstrate this, it suffices to put .
6. Dual Characterization
In this section, we will provide some dual characterization of injective Banach lattices. To start with, we reveal the structure of the dual space. Below, and stand for the topological dual of X and the natural duality pairing between X and .
Definition 7. The -dual of a lattice normed vector space X over Λ is defined as the lattice normed vector space over Λ, where consists of all linear operators from X to Λ such that there exists with for all . The least λ satisfying the above is denoted by . The mixed norm on X is determined, as usual, by .
Definition 8. A -complete -space will be referred to as --space. An M-norm is a -valued norm on X satisfying for all .
Theorem 6. Let X be a -complete ordered Banach space, let be the Boolean valued representation of X, and . Then the following are equivalent:
X is an injective Banach lattice with isomorphic to .
is an -space within .
is a Banach–Kantorovich lattice with a Λ-valued M-norm.
is a --space.
Proof. By
Section 2,
X is an injective Banach lattice with
if and only if
is an
-space
. By the duality between
- and
-spaces which was discovered by Ellis [
29] (Theorem 6.4) and the transfer principle,
X is an injective Banach lattice with
if and only if
is an
-space
. Hence, (1) ⟺ (2). By
Section 2 and [
11] (Lemma 3.5),
is a Banach–Kantorovich lattice if and only if
is a Banach lattice
. Moreover, it is immediate from the properties of descents that
is an
-norm
if and only if
is an
-valued
M-norm, whence (2) ⟺ (3). Since a decomposable lattice normed vector space is order complete if and only if it is disjointly complete and relatively uniformly complete [
19] (Theorem 2.3.2). Also, a vector space with a mixed norm is a Banach space if and only if the corresponding lattice normed vector space is complete under the norm
-convergence [
19] (7.1.2). It follows that
is a Banach–Kantorovich lattice if and only if
is a Banach lattice. To demonstrate the equivalence (3) ⟺ (4), it suffices to show that
and
are or are not
M-norms simultaneously. Assume that
ia an
M-norm, but
for some
. Then there are
and
such that
Taking
-norms, we obtain
This is a contradiction. The converse is obvious. □
Lemma 13. Let X and Y be Dedekind complete vector lattices and let Φ be a Maharam operator from X to Y. Then for every regular operator with there exists an orthomorphism such that and for all .
Proof. This is a special case of the Radon–Nikodým Theorem for regular operators due to Luxemburg and Schep; see [
33]. □
Lemma 14. Let X, Y, and Φ be the same as in Lemma 2. Then there exists an f-algebra isomorphism h from onto the order complete f-subalgebra of such that holds for all and .
Proof. This is an obvious consequence of [
19] (Theorem 3.4.10). □
Lemma 15. If is a Banach space associated with a Banach–Kantorovich space over Λ,
then is associated with the Banach–Kantorovich space , where the Λ
-valued norm of is defined asIn particular, and for all and . Proof. See [
19] (Theorem 7.1.4). □
Theorem 7. Let X be an injective Banach lattice with and let Φ be a strictly positive Maharam operator from X to with the Levi property such that for all . Then
For every there is a unique orthomorphism such that for all ;
is a --space and the mapping is a -isometry from onto ;
is a lattice -isometry from onto a majorizing sublattice of ;
For all ; in particular, belongs to the -closure of .
Proof. If then for some . As is a Maharam operator as well, there is such that and by Lemma 13. Considering that and putting , we arrive at 7(1). The strict positivity of implies the uniqueness of w as well as the simultaneous positivity of and w. Thus, the mapping is a lattice isomorphism from onto . By Lemma 14 we can identify with an order closed sub-f-algebra of and define the -valued norm on as . Then the regular norm on is a mixed norm: for all . It is clear from the above that if and only if so that . Consequently, , whence 7(2) holds.
The remaining part of the proof rests upon Lemma 15. Since
is interval preserving,
is a lattice homomorphism; see [
16] (Theorem 2.19). Moreover, considering that
and
is
-linear, we deduce that
So,
is isometric and
-linear. Now, 7(3) is immediate from the relations
valid for all
and
, according to which
. Define the continuous seminorm
and the sublinear operator
as
and
. By the Hahn–Banach–Kantorovich Theorem [
16] (Theorem 1.25) for an arbitrary
there exists a linear operator
such that
and
for all
. It follows that
S is regular,
, and by Lemma 13 there exists an orthomorphism
with
for all
and
. Moreover,
and we see that
Finally, we conclude that
lies in the dual closed unit ball of the seminorm
p and this unit ball is the
-closure of
. □
We preface the next result with a few remarks. Denote by
the part of
consisting of
-continuous projections. Let
stand for the part of
consisting of all continuous
-linear operators from
to
. Since
is an
-spaces and
has the Levi property, every norm bounded linear operator from
to
is regular. Hence,
coincides with
; see [
34] (Theorem 3.5). Moreover,
is a Dedekind complete Banach lattice. Now, every weak
-continuous linear operator from
to
is norm continuous and
is considered as a subspace of
with the induced ordering.
Theorem 8. Let X be a Banach lattice, a complete Boolean algebra, and . Then the following are equivalent:
(1) X is injective with .
(2) The four conditions hold:
- (a)
is isomorphic to a complete subalgebra of the Boolean algebra .
- (b)
There exists a lattice -isometry such that is a majorizing sublattice of .
- (c)
For every there exists such that , , and lie in the -closure of .
- (d)
is a --space with J as an order unit.
Proof. : An injective Banach lattice
X is representable as
, where
is a strictly positive Maharam operator with the Levi property and
; see 2.8. It is also clear that a band projection
of
X lies in
if and only if the adjoint
lies in
. Moreover,
is
-continuous. It follows that the mapping
is a Boolean isomorphism from
onto
. Put
and observe that
J is a lattice isomorphism [
16] (Theorem 2.20) and
J is an isometry:
Thus, we have established
and
, while
and
follow from Theorem 7.
: Assume that are fulfilled. From it follows that is isomorphic to as every projection in is of the form with and the mapping is a norm preserving Boolean isomorphism from into . Similarly, is Boolean isomorphic to . Below it is convenient to identify all these five Boolean algebras.
According to
there exists a positive operator
with
. Thus
is norm bounded and almost interval preserving by [
18] (Theorem 1.4.19(ii)). Moreover,
as
J is an isomorphism. Assuming that
and using
, for an arbitrary
we may pick
with
so that
, whence
and
is strictly positive. Thus we can define the
-valued norm on
X as follows:
. Evidently
as
and, as we will see later, the reverse inequality holds as well. Note that the norm
is decomposable; i.e.,
for all
and
Indeed, for
,
, and
we have
, whence
.
Using
, we also define the
-valued norm on
by putting
where
and
, so that
. The definition is sound, since this
is unique. Indeed, if
and
for
; then
and
. It follows that
and, since
is an
-space,
, so that
. Now, taking into account the inequality
we deduce
and
for all
as claimed.
We will show that the Banach lattices and are lattice -isometric. Each is an adjoint operator, i.e., for some continuous operator . Moreover, in this event for we have if and only if . Thus, the mapping is an order preserving isometry from onto . This isometry is -linear, since , where denotes a band projection in as well as the corresponding projections in and . It remains to refer to Theorem 6 to conclude that X is an injective Banach lattice. □
Remark 4. It should be emphasized that the sublattice in admits a contractive positive projection. Indeed, there is an order continuous lattice isomorphism such that ; see [19] (Theorem 3.4.10). Therefore, and is a contractive positive projection to with . Remark 5. In [7] (Proposition 3B) Haydon made the observation: If two hereditary downwards faces and of , the positive part of the dual unit ball, have the properties (1) and are -closed, (2) each admits a unique representation with and , (3) for all and ; then there exists such that and . Of course in this case . Using this fact, item of Theorem 8, can be formulated in terms of the facial structure of . 7. Concluding Remarks
The geometric study of an
-predual space, a Banach space whose dual is isometric (isomorphic) to an
-space, stems from the works of Grothendieck [
35] and Lindenstrauss [
36]. The integral representation theorems of Choquet led quite naturally to exploration of the related geometric structure of state spaces; see Alfsen [
37]. One of the main problems in operator algebras is the geometric description of state spaces of operator algebras; the complete solution of this problem by Alfsen, Hanche-Olsen, Iohum, and Shultz is presented in the book [
38]. One of the recent valuable developments is the classification of
facially symmetric spaces which was initiated by Friedman and Rousso in [
39]. In particular, the geometric description of an
-space as a strongly facially symmetric spaces given by Ibragimov and Kudaybergenov in [
40] admits a counterpart for injective Banach lattices. This development of convexity theory has motivated the geometric study of the duals and preduals of injective Banach lattices.
In [
41] (Corollary 1) Fremlin proved that a Banach lattice
X is isomorphic to an
L-space if and only if every continuous linear operator from
X to
is order bounded. To formulate the Boolean version of this result, we define the Boolean counterpart of the Banach lattice
. Suppose that
Q is the Stone representation space of
and
X is a Banach lattice. Denote by
the set of cosets of continuous vector-functions
such that
is a meager set in
Q and the continuous extension
of the pointwise norm
to the whole of
Q belongs to the Banach lattice
of continuous functions. Vector-functions
u and
v are equivalent if
for all
. If
is the coset of
u then we define
and
. The set
is naturally endowed with the structure of a
-complete Banach lattice; see 2.5. Moreover,
is an injective Banach lattice whose Boolean valued representation is
within
. Now, interpreting the Fremlin characterization of
L-spaces in the model
, we arrive at the following result.
Theorem 9. For a -cyclic Banach lattice X the following are equivalent:
(1) There is a countable partition of unity in such that is lattice -isomorphic to an injective Banach lattice for every .
(2) Every continuous -linear operator from X to is order bounded.
If the dual
of a Banach lattice
X is injective, then the pair
with the conventional duality pairing admits a nice Boolean valued representation as a dual pair
with
injective in an appropriate Boolean valued universe
; see [
11] (Theorem 3.8 and Corollary 3.9). Nevertheless, there is a striking asymmetry in these dualities: If a Banach lattice
X is injective, then the duality between
X and
is not representable as Boolean valued duality between
and
; see Theorem 6. The reason is that for a dual space
the Boolean algebra of
M-projections is isomorphic to the complete Boolean algebra of
L-projections on
X, whilst the collection of
M-projections on
X may be too scarce; see [
42] (Theorems I.1.10 and V.4.6).
Theorem 7 can be viewed as a version for injective Banach lattices of Grothendieck’s result stating that a Banach space is an
-space provided that its dual is isomorphic to a Banach space of continuous functions on a locally compact space vanishing at infinity (see [
43] (Theorem 27.4.1)); in other words,
is the only predual of
(see [
35] ([Theorem 1)). As can be seen, the proof consists of a combination of Boolean valued representation and some results of the standard structure theory of Banach lattices. Another version of Grothendieck’s result for injective Banach lattices in terms of the
-dual
(Definition 7) can be obtained by the direct Boolean valued interpretation [
9] (Theorem 5.12).