The Primal Scream: Re-Reading the “Temporality” Chapter of Phenomenology of Perception in the Context of Negative Philosophy
Abstract
:1. Introduction
I think Beauvoir’s claim that the human condition is at stake in this earlier work is not an exaggeration. The theory of time that will later become negative philosophy, in the end, does more than touch on classical issues like past and future, being, and the meaning of thought; precisely because it addresses these, it also communicates something about what it means to live—not only to be biologically alive but to assume our thrownness into the world and carry it into the precarity of the future, “the human condition”. I do not think it is a coincidence, therefore, that the theory of time offered in Phenomenology of Perception, a theory that will eventually make the concept of negative philosophy possible, leads directly into reflections on “the movement of a life”. Contrary to the classical view that insists on time’s essential quantifiability, αριθμός, and likewise, counter to the view that time is an “abstract” condition of possibility or even a transcendental origin—“positive time”—it is, instead, an event unfolded between birth and death with the essential shape of the life that is lived. This shape, however, is not that of the λόγος that would assign each event its Grund, nor that of a perfect harmony or diapason. As the principle of a negative philosophy, “negative time” unfolds as le cri—the primal scream according to which this life and all others come to pass. To reject Eleatism is at the same time to reject the principle that would hold being together as being, that would secure its purity and difference from nothing. There is no λόγος, no diapason or final harmony according to which all things would be assigned their names and proper place—there is only the primal scream where sense dissolves into non-sense and where the event of sense is only the inverse or envelope of this disarticulateness.It is therefore of extreme importance … to give back to man this childish audacity that years of verbal submission [have] taken away: the audacity to say: ‘I am here.’ This is why The Phenomenology of Perception by Maurice Merleau-Ponty is not only a remarkable specialist work but a book that is of interest to the whole of man and to every man; the human condition is at stake in this book ([5] p. 164).
- The positive concept of time and eloquence
Again, for Augustine, only the present/presence is—the future is not yet; the past is no more. Time must, therefore, be thought in its positivity as the successive assertion of the present, its “repetition”6, as the future transitions into the present and the present into the past. Only the temporal present allows for phenomenological presence—the future as such and the past as such cannot appear, since they are not. All presence, then, must be a function of the temporal present: the past appears in the temporal present in the form of memory; the future appears in the temporal present in the form of expectation. It would not be “appropriate” to speak of past and future independently of their appearance in the present, since they are, for Augustine, non-experienceable. The three times that “truly are”, are the three temporal ecstases insofar as, in every case, they are organized by the present. As in Aristotle, for Augustine, time must be now or be nothing.Now it is apparent and clear to say that there are neither futures nor pasts; nor is it appropriate to say that there are three times: past, present, and future. It would be more appropriate to say: there are these three times, a presence of the past [praesens de praeteritis], a presence of the present [praesens de praesentibus], and a presence of the future [praesens de futuris]. For there are three kinds of things in the soul [anima], and I do not see them elsewhere: the present memory of the past, the present thought of the present, the present expectation of the future. If we are allowed to speak thus, I see and admit that there are three times, that three times truly are ([8] Book XI, p. 223).
This fragment is arguably the origin of the identification between the temporal present and phenomenological presence that, in Aristotle and Augustine, produces the positive, assertoric theory of time. Non-being, because it is not, can be neither phenomenologically present nor temporally in the present. To say that non-being is phenomenologically present would be to say that what is not could be a possible object of experience. But how could this be since my experiential field is populated by objects, that is to say, by beings. Non-being, then, could only be, at best, derived from being—the absence of a being that, as it were, was supposed to be there. Now Parmenides will simply reject the proposition that non-being is any way phenomenologically available, and this seems to be what is entailed by his insistence on its unthinkability. Non-being, by definition, cannot be a possible object of experience; therefore, my experiential field must be filled with being(s) only. Likewise, non-being, because it is unthinkable, must also in principle be uncountable, and the fragment under consideration seems to make this clear. If being had come into being, then there would be some prior time where it was not—but this would mean that being was, earlier, non-being, and this is impossible. Likewise, if it were subject to temporal decay, there would be some future time where it would not be, and, again, this is impossible. Therefore, being can be subject neither to temporal generation nor decay. However, we could still put being on a line where it moves through time but without any kind of change (eternity as “temporal” passage without change). It seems to be here that we encounter the origins of positive time: if the thinkability of being is dependent on its immunity to generation and decay, then its thinkability depends on its continual and repeated presence in the temporal now. For it to be thinkable, i.e., phenomenologically present, it must, in every case, be now. If time is, it must be now, even as the infinite repetition of nows.It never was nor will be, since it is now, all together, one, continuous. For what birth will you seek for it? How and whence did it grow? I shall not allow you to say nor to think from not being: for it is not to be said nor thought that it is not; and what need would have driven it later rather than earlier, beginning from nothing to grow? Nor will the force of conviction allow anything besides it to come to be even from not being ([10] pp. 249–250).
Whether Hegel and Bergson are fairly inserted into this tradition is a question we will leave aside, even if Heidegger believed this to be the case. What concerns us is: (1) is there another, “tasteful” tradition of time (we will also leave aside the question as to whether Heidegger would rightly be included in any tradition qualified as “tasteful”); this other tradition, rather than beginning from the prioritization of presence/the present, would be a “negative” account of time. That is, rather than thinking time as the assertion of presence, which organizes all other temporal ecstases, this other tradition would attempt to think time from non-presence. Rather than being a function of an asserted presence/present, the absent moments would articulate the given—the given (presence/present) would be a function of what is not given (non-presence/not-in-the-present) rather than the other way around. Rather than a succession of presences, nows, time would be a succession of “negativities” of which the now would “merely” be the reverse. Rather than “articulation”, this account of time would operate as “disarticulation”.[Heidegger in Being and Time] is trying to criticize the idea of time as a uniform, linear and infinite series of “now-points”. On this model… the future is the not-yet-now, the past is the no-longer-now, and the present is the now that flows from future to past at each passing moment. This is what Heidegger calls the “vulgar” or ordinary conception of time where priority is always given to the present. Heidegger thinks that this Aristotelian conception of time has dominated philosophical inquiries into time from the ancient Greeks to Hegel and even up to his near contemporary Bergson [11].
- B.
- Negative time and disarticulateness
There is no such thing as the positive value of the “sign”—or even the visible thing before me. The sign as well as its visible referent become articulated as the other side of a διαίρεσις—a splitting, division, indeed, a differentiation within which there is a lacuna, a crack—an écart, that allows the sides of the division to be10. The sign, as well as its referent, therefore, have their meaning in virtue of a variation rather than an assertion. We might take this a step further and suggest that “they are”—not in virtue of their being-as-presence—but in virtue of the splits, divisions and cracks that differentiate them, not only from other beings, but from “themselves” as well. The response to Eleatism is to point out that there is no τὸ ἐόν (what-is), neither metaphysically nor phenomenologically—there is only difference, the ῥέω, “becoming”. This indicates a Heraclitean, apophatic tradition of thinking time, opposed to the Eleatic, “vulgar” tradition of positive time.According to this model of meaning, there is no positive value of identities or visibles; they have their value only because of their negative value or separation from every other identity or visible. Just as in the diacritical system of signs words mean what they mean in deviation from other words that they are not and there is no single word that explains all words, in the diacritical ontology, the nothing of consciousness and being deviate from one another and at no place do they turn into one another or come from the same source ([15] pp. 372–393).
Negative theology, also known as “apophatic theology”, includes any theological approach to articulating or speaking about God that proceeds via negativa, by way of negativity.13 The term “apophatic” comes from αποφατικός, “negative”. The stem, φατικός, roughly translates as “assertion” and comes from the verb φημί, “to speak”. The prefix, απο-, roughly means “away from”, so to “negate” in this sense is literally “to speak away from”. We cannot speak of what God is so must speak “away” from what God is—speak only of what God is not. The divine is ineffable—beyond all possible speech—and, therefore, beyond any possible sign. God, then, is simply the obverse, the negative of everything it is not, the shadow, as it were, cast by the discourse of created being, precisely, what God is not. Merleau-Ponty proposes to establish a “negative philosophy” where, removing God or replacing it with “being”, ontology also becomes a via negativa or, as he says, “indirect”. The expressed is only the double, the obverse, or the reverse, of what is not expressed—Σιγή, “silence”, the abyss.I will finally be able to take a position in ontology, as the introduction demands, and specify its theses exactly, only after the series of reductions the book develops and which are all in the first one, but also are really accomplished only the last one. This reversal itself—circulus vitiosus deus11—is not hesitation, bad faith and bad dialectic, but return to Σιγή, the abyss12. One cannot make a direct ontology. My ‘indirect’ method (being in the beings) is also conformed with being----“negative philosophy” like “negative theology” ([1] p. 179).
To posit an origin—specifically an assertoric or positive one—that founds Being and puts it forward is, apparently, the mark of “essentialist thinking”, which could be understood to code Hegelio-Sartreanism. Such a foundation establishes a Being that is purified of nothingness and, thus, opposes it absolutely. What if, however, behind Being there were no assertoric foundation but only a “negative ontological base”? In this case, Being does not come forth from a transcendental origin—it is not and cannot be founded on an assertion that would make it possible. Rather Being comes forth from a certain lack or lacuna, “negated nothingness”, i.e., “not nothing”, “non-hidden Being”. In other words, Being would be the inverse, the “lining” or “envelope”, as Merleau-Ponty liked to say, of an origin that gives Being only in its withdraw, concealment, and absence. The visible is only the shadow of the invisible that it is not.It always assumes essentialist thinking—according to which there is something that in the last resort makes Being emerge—a necessary foundation, i.e., essential for [the] there is [il y a], a nail that anchors and establishes Being as absolutely opposed to Nothingness. Behind eminent Being there is a negative ontological base, as we say negative theology: demonstration of Being as what has surmounted, negated nothingness. This “not nothing” gives eminent Being only if we conceive of it starting with nothing. We must conceive of being from not nothing: non-hidden Being ([19] p. 50).14
The negative is not “beyond” and not a “second positive order” as it is for the Hegelio-Sartrean understanding of it. The “positive” order requires another one that is its double, that is beneath it. Not removed (transcendent) with respect to it but where we only access the positive through the negative (and the negative through the positive). Where the negative is the invisible lining of the positive-visible, and where we proceed toward the visible only through the invisible, by way of a specifically philosophical via negativa. This “negative philosophy” is “true philosophy” and is the other of “official philosophy” ([20] pp. 9, 93, 261), not “philosophical” but “a-philosophical”. In this respect, we may very well describe negativity as the a-positive (and positivity as the a-negative).It’s not a matter of a fight between philosophy and its adversaries (positivism), but of a philosophy that wants to be philosophy by being non-philosophy—of a “negative philosophy” (in the sense of “negative theology”), which opens access to the absolute, not as “beyond”, second positive order, but as another order that requires what is beneath, the double, accessible only through it—true philosophy mocks philosophy, is a-philosophy ([20] p. 173).
Without belaboring Merleau-Ponty’s dialogue with Husserl’s time diagram from the Zeitbewußtsein lectures, we can highlight some significant motifs found in this text. The first notable thing is Merleau-Ponty’s denial that there even are the temporal ecstases of “past”, “present”, and “future”, at least insofar as we understand these to be fully distinguishable. The temporal profiles are rather intrinsically connected, and we cannot have one without the others. What there is, rather, is a unified phenomenon of passage, where the ecstases of past, present, and future are names for temporal points of view that look out onto a single phenomenon. Because there are no distinct ecstases, using the word “succession” in reference to this phenomenon is not entirely accurate. “Succession” is usually understood to be a series of distinct units, and if there actually are no distinct units, there can be no temporal succession as such. This is clearly a very radical claim. If there is no temporal succession, how do we account for time as passage—if not passage as succession, then passage as what? Rather than succession, there is a “rupture” or “disintegration” of temporal profiles, one into the other, where one emerges out of the other in simultaneity. This “continuous emission” of temporal ecstases is precisely a movement of integration–disintegration. The disintegration of the future is the integration of the present; the disintegration of the present is the integration of the past, which in turn disintegrates into temporally sedimented moments, which, in turn, integrate the present and the future. The first one describes the passage from protention to primal impression; the second the passage from primal impression to retention. The retentions, in turn, integrate the present, the present integrates the future.What there is in reality, is not a past, a present, a future, not discrete instants A, B, and C, nor really distinct Abschattungen [profiles] …. The springing forth [jaillisement] of a new present does not cause a settlement [tassement] of the past and an upheaval [secousse] of the future: the new present is the passage of future into the present, and of the former present to the past; it is as a single movement from one end to the other that time begins to move. The “instants” … do not exist in succession but differentiate themselves from each other…. When we pass from [instant] B to C, there is something like a rupture, a disintegration of B into B`, and of A into A`; and C itself which, when it was about to arrive, was anticipated by a continuous emission of Abschattungen, has no sooner arrived than it begins to lose its substance…. [Temporal ecstases] are interconnected, not by a synthesis of identification, which would congeal [figerait] them at a point in time, but by a transition-synthesis (Übergangssynthesis), in so far as they emerge [sortent], one from the other, and each of these projections is merely one aspect of the total rupture [éclatement] or dehiscence ([14] pp. 442–443).
“Originary presence” is another dimension of what is “not present”, where the lacuna, the gap, articulates the world and its visibility. This negative is the principle of transcendence, being out of place and out of joint, never coinciding but being in every case “late”. The joints between things, the connections, are at the same time “disjunctions” where the σύνθεσις, the bringing together of things, is always at the same time their “dismemberment”.where its absence counts in the world (it is “behind” the visible, imminent or eminent visibility, it is Ur-prasentiert [originally presented] precisely as Nichturprasentierbar [not originally present], as another dimension) where the lacuna that marks its place is one of the points of passage of the “world”. It is this negative that makes possible the vertical world, the union of the incompossibles, the being in transcendence, and the topological space and the time in joints and members, in dis-junction and dismembering ([1] p. 228).
Standing out against the invisible profiles of birth and death, past and future, we are as much condemned to live as we are condemned to freedom (Sartre) or condemned to sense (Merleau-Ponty). In other words, a life unfolds only in its temporal passage. Death, the possibility of the disintegration yet to come, can only ever be one side of a life that was lived, no matter how long or how short. And likewise, a life in every case comes on the heels of the event (or advent) of its birth. Life, then, is only the “transition” between these two disarticulate poles, past and future, birth and death. As transition, life too is auto-constituting, and I am condemned to live the life I have been born into—it will unfold in its own simultaneity, because of and in spite of my decisions. There is no external, transcendental principle that makes a life possible. The unfolding of its sense is not the consequent thought or even “accomplishment” of some prior or a priori “thinker”. Whatever meaning it has does not come from on high but is autochthonously brought forth only in the living of it. This is why no one’s life ever is or has a “perfect moment”17—not because of a radical, unconditioned freedom, but because we will live through our lives (or our lives will live through us). As Paul Valery says in Introduction to the Method of Leonardo da Vinci:The synthesis of time is a transition synthesis; it is the movement of a life which unfolds, and there is no other manner of effectuating it than of living this life; there is no place of time; it is time which carries itself and launches itself forward. Time as indivisible thrust and as transition alone can make possible time as successive multiplicity, and what we place at the origin of intra-temporality is a constituting time ([14] pp. 446–447).
No thought is such that it destroys, and concludes, the power of thinking—there is no given position of the bolt which closes the lock forever. And there is no thought that is, for thought, a resolution born of its very development, and like a final harmony from this permanent dissonance ([14] p. 421).
2. Conclusions: The Primal Scream
If time is the vehicle of both the world’s sense as well as its non-sense, then expression, which includes the life that is lived, is a function of time’s passage. This seems to follow from what Merleau-Ponty has said about transition synthesis. The λόγος as word is, in this case, the articulation and integration of a scream—the first word (for the child, for the painter) does not result from a transcendental origin that organizes its sense; it emerges as the negative, the disintegrative sense of the scream. In the same way that a life unfolds only in its living, expression and sense are also temporal events of passage, the shadow of an unexpressed non-sense. Likewise, the sense of the world and expression is never underwritten by a transcendental origin that would guarantee and secure it. Sense and expression are, “like a step taken in the fog” ([26] p. 8), precarious institutions that must be maintained in “repetition” and sedimentation. The λόγος exists only when there is speech and expression, and without them, there can only be silence and chaos. The λόγος as reason is, similarly, the negative, the articulation and integration of an un-reason that is in every case its double. All rationalities are thus haunted and threatened by the specific forms of irrationality that they produce and from which they emerge. Like the life that is lived, sense and reason are born—in speech, in action—and are thrown towards the essential possibility of their disintegration.[The artist] speaks as the first man spoke and paints as if no one had ever painted before. What he expresses cannot, therefore, be the translation of a clearly defined thought, since such clear thoughts are those which have already been uttered by ourselves or by others … There is nothing but a vague fever before the act of artistic expression, and only the work itself, completed and understood, is proof that there was something rather than nothing to be said … the artist launches his work just as man once launched the first word, not knowing whether it will be anything more than a scream [cri]… The meaning of what the artist is going to say does not exist anywhere—not in things, which as yet have no meaning, nor in the artist himself, in his unformulated life. It summons one away from the already constituted reason in which ‘cultural men’ are content to shut themselves, toward a reason which contains its own origins ([26] p. 40).
The life that is lived and all expressivity are the “the scream of light” that emerges from the “permanent dissonance” of being. “Like time passes”, this primal scream is the shadow and invisibility of the λόγος, the word and reason, that haunts it. The scream becomes word and madness reason and each, in turn, disintegrates into the disarticulate “origin” that it already was or that it carried with it or that, at every instance, made it possible.There is no alternative between lived experience and the spoken unless one omits the articulation of lived experience, organization around a tacit sense, the sensorial fields where every individual is already a variant of a dimension, an exemplar of an a-logical essence, what Hermes Trismegistus has called “the scream of light” in order to reduce lived experience to pure muteness and contiguity, and if one omits, moreover, the presuppositions of speech, the establishment, for example, of a linguistic field that envelops every possible being in the order of the nameable and expressible. If, on the contrary, one knows how to find in both orders these institutions of the same thought, then there is no longer a choice between them: from lived experience to the spoken there is agreement through reversal, chiasm and one can say, with Husserl, that philosophy is ‘still mute experience, that it is a matter of bringing to pure expression its proper sense,’ that is, that philosophy speaks and that its speech leans against silence, that it speaks from the inside of being and not from on high or from afar, that it speaks especially of itself, that is to say, of speech, that it speaks like the trees grow, like time passes and like human beings speak ([20] p. 246).
The habits of the everyday, the concepts of modern philosophy, carry with them and in every case implicate a philosophical outlook, whether they mean to or not. These abstractions, which nonetheless structure and articulate the unfolding of experience in the everyday, become destabilized by a certain kind of thinking that endeavors to express something else—“the movement of life”, “belief in things in the world and in our own presence”, “experience”, “the birth of meaning”, etc. There are surely many other ways Merleau-Ponty and others have attempted to name this… whatever it is that common sense, the obvious, the power of public opinion, ideology, indeed, what even philosophy forgets. Whatever we want to call it—silence, this mute experience—Merleau-Ponty’s works seem organized around this most fundamental of philosophical projects: to say what has not been said and, perhaps, what is not permitted to be said; to make visible what is as of yet unseen, indeed, the childish audacity to not only say “I am here” but also to imagine a present and a future that the wisdom of both common sense and the philosophers tell us is impossible. I do not think this audacity is unique to Merleau-Ponty, but I think Beauvoir was right—we indeed find it in his works—as we find it in any philosopher worthy of the name and worth reading. If we are going to read and interpret philosophy, I think we do ourselves a disservice if we do this with any other aim than to make this audacity, unique to each thinker, as visible as possible, and I doubt very much that organizing an interpretation around “breaks” or even “development” helps this process. The expression of philosophical audacity, rather, takes the form of desquamation, shedding one’s skin, a process that never ends in a fully developed “system” but, where, in each case, one becomes disarticulated in the midst of the primal scream.The intention [of the The Visible and the Invisible] is to direct the reader toward a domain which his habits of thought do not make immediately accessible to him. It is a question, in particular, of persuading him that the fundamental concepts of modern philosophy—for example the distinctions between subject and object, essence and fact, being and nothingness, the notions of consciousness, image, thing, which are in constant use—already implicate a singular interpretation of the world and cannot lay claim to a special dignity when our intention is precisely to go back to face our experience, in order to seek the birth of meaning ([1] pp. xxvi–xxvii).
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Sixteen if we count from Merleau-Ponty’s death in 1961. The Visible and the Invisible was published posthumously in 1964. |
2 | The “philosophy of negativity” refers specifically to Sartre and probably to Hegel as well; not to be confused with what Merleau-Ponty calls “negative philosophy,” which will be the focus here. |
3 | I don’t want to belabor this question as it stands in set theory and philosophy of mathematics. On the other hand, zero does have cardinality in the sense that it represents a set with zero members. Eleatism, and the theories of time we find in Aristotle and Augustine (and others), I think assume the non-cardinality of zero, i.e., nothingness. Because nothingness is not, it cannot be counted. This is, of course, a matter deserving more attention than can be given here. |
4 | In the Timaeus, the eponymous character gives this definition of time—χρόνος—in his description of the origins of the kosmos: [The mythological creator of the cosmos] designed to make it resemble its pattern [παράδειγμα] still more closely. Accordingly, seeing that the pattern is an eternal organism [ζῶον ἀίδιον], He set about making this Universe, so far as He could, of a like kind. But inasmuch as the nature of the organism was eternal, this quality was impossible to attach in its entirety to what is generated; wherefore He planned to make a moveable image of Eternity, and as He set in order the Heaven, of that Eternity which abides in unity He made an eternal image, moving according to number [ἀριθμὸν], even that which we have named time [χρόνον] ([7] 37d-e). |
5 | Aristotle discussion of “void” occupies a substantial set of chapters in Book IV of the Physics, and the discussion is too involved to go into here. Suffice it to say that Aristotle denies the existence of void, which I think is quite uncontroversial. It also seems evident, however, that the discussion the denial of void is an important reason why, later, time is conceptualized in terms of the present. If there is no void, we can only speak of what is, i.e., what is present now. |
6 | Repetition of the same, where “same” designates the same of presence/the present. In Deleuze, where repetition is the repetition of difference, we get a concept of time very different from the Parmenidian-Augustinian tradition. That, of course, will have to be taken up elsewhere. |
7 | We can also think about how the positive concept of time underwrites empiricist epistemology. It seems important that Hume, for example, identifies the vivacity of the sense impression with its presence to the mind (in the present) and that, likewise, the idea is a faded copy of the impression that loses its vivacity precisely by being past. It would be interesting to bring this into dialogue with Deleuze’s reading of Hume in Empiricism and Subjectivity. To what extent does a transcendental empiricism presuppose or challenge the positive concept of time? All of this would have to be taken up elsewhere. |
8 | The view supported here is at variance with most interpretations of Merleau-Ponty, time, and musicality. The emphasis is typically placed on the various references we find across Merleau-Ponty’s text to singing, voice, melody and so forth—and of course there are many texts that support this. According to this prevailing approach, Merleau-Ponty is placed within a “consonant” tradition of thinking. There are, however, also numerous references to le cri—the cry, shout, or scream, in Merleau-Ponty. I don’t think Merleau-Ponty (or any thinker) is under an obligation to use consistent imagery, and I suspect that, in the end, Merleau-Ponty was a thinker of both consonance as well as dissonance. See, for example, Jessica Wiskus, [12] and Ted Toadvine [13]. |
9 | I go into more detail addressing Merleau-Ponty’s theory of sense-genesis in Whitmoyer, K. [4]; See especially chapter 4, “Le sentir du sens”. |
10 | “Diacritic” come from the Greek, Διαίρεσις, which we recognize from Aristotle. The prefix, δια-, refers to both a separation as well as a mutual relationship. The stem, αἱρέω, means “to grasp.” So we get the image of something being torn in opposite directions. The gloss added by Merleau-Ponty is that the positive and oppositional poles, the thing being torn in two, is as much of a function of the splitting open as it is the poles. Indeed, the two poles only become poles in virtue of the splitting between them. |
11 | This appears to be a reference to aphorism 56 of Beyond Good and Evil. Kaufmann suggests either “a vicious circle made of God” or “God is a vicious circle.” See Nietzsche, F. ([16] p. 68). |
12 | The “return to Σιγή, the abyss” references Paul Claudel’s Art poétique. The full passage reads: “Time is the means offered to all that which will be to be, in order to be no more. It is the Invitation to death, to each phrase to decompose in the explanatory and total harmony, to consummate the speech [parole] of adoration in the ear of Sigé [silence], the Abyss.” Translation by the author. See Claudel, P. ([17] p. 61). |
13 | Some work on the significance of negative theology for 20th Century French philosophy has been done. See, for example, Bradley, A. [18]. The book mostly focuses on Derrida. Merleau-Ponty is mentioned once but there is no discussion of the references to negative theology in The Visible and the Invisible. |
14 | Quoted by Barbaras, R. ([19] p. 50); also by Kaushik, R. ([15] p. 377). Compare to this passage in The Visible and the Invisible: “On the one hand, one seeks being and nothingness in the pure state, one wishes to approach them as closely as possible, one aims at being itself in its plenitude and nothingness itself in its vacuity, one presses the confused experience until one draws the entity and the negentity out of it, one squeezes it between them as between pincers; beyond the visible one trusts entirely in what we think under the terms of being and nothingness, one practices an ‘essentialist’ thought which refers to significations beyond experience, and thus one constructs our relations with the world” ([1] p. 86). |
15 | I have discussed Merleau-Ponty’s reading of the time diagram in detail elsewhere. See Whitmoyer, K. [4] “Temporality Disparue” as well as Whitmoyer, K. [22]. I’ve removed most of the explicit reference to the temporal moments represented on the time diagram as A, B, and C for the sake of readability and to foreground aspects of this text that I think are important beyond Merleau-Ponty’s engagement with Husserl. |
16 | Husserl mentions this concept explicitly in Erfahrung und Urteil although Merleau-Ponty does not cite a text. See Husserl, E. ([23] pp. 213, 224, 229, 230). |
17 | In Sartre’s Nausea the character Anny, at least for a while, conceptualizes her life in terms of “perfect moments.” See Sartre, J.-P. [25]. |
18 | For example, As Merleau-Ponty notes in the 1961 course, “Cartesian Ontology and Ontology Today,” Klee’s colors emanate as though through profound natural phenomena, “exhaled in the right spot,” like a patina or moisture—“inarticulate scream [cri inarticulé] . . . that seemed to be the voice of light” (Hermes Trismegistus)” ([20] p. 99); also in a draft of a chapter from The Visible and the Invisible, “exemplar of an alogical essence, what Hermes Trismegistus called ‘the scream [cri] of light’” ([20] p. 246). Merleau-Ponty also makes reference to the same remark by Hermes Trismegistus in “Eye and Mind:” “Art is not construction, artifice, industrious relation to a space and to a world of the outside. It is truly the ‘inarticulate scream,’ as Hermes Trismegistus said, ‘which seemed the voice of the light.’ And, once there, it awakens in ordinary vision dormant powers, a secret of preexistence” ([21] pp. 370–371, trans. Modified). |
References
- Merleau-Ponty, M. The Visible and the Invisible; Lefort, C., Ed.; Lingis, A., Translator; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1968. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. The Primacy of Perception; Edie, J.M., Ed. and Translator; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1964. [Google Scholar]
- Barbaras, R. The Being of the Phenomenon; Toadvine, T.; Lawlor, L., Translators; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Whitmoyer, K. The Philosophy of Ontological Lateness: Merleau-Ponty and the Tasks of Thinking; Bloomsbury: London, UK, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- de Beauvoir, S. A Review of Phenomenology of Perception by Maurice Merleau-Ponty. In Philosophical Writings; Simons, M.A., Timmerman, M., Mader, M.B., Eds.; Timmerman, M., Translator; The University of Illinois Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. Physics, Volume I: Books 1–4; Wicksteed, P.K., Translator; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. Timaeus; Bury, R.G., Translator; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Augustine. Confessions; Sheed, F.J., Translator; Hackett: Cambridge, UK, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Hume. Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and the Principles of Morals; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Kirk, G.S.; Raven, J.E.; Schofield, M. Parmenides, fr. 8. In The Presocratic Philosophers; Kirk, G.S., Raven, J.E., Schofield, M., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Critchley, S. Heidegger’s Being and Time Part 8: Temporality. The Guardian. 2009. Available online: https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/belief/2009/jul/27/heidegger-being-time-philosophy (accessed on 25 September 2024).
- Wiskus, J. From the Body to the Melody: ‘Relearning’ the Experience of Time in the Later Merleau-Ponty. Avant Trends in Interdiscip. Stud. 2018, 9, 129–140. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Toadvine, T. Singing the World in a New Key: Merleau-Ponty and the Ontology of Sense. Janus Head 2004, 7, 273–283. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Phenomenology of Perception; Routledge & Kegan Paul: London, UK, 1945. [Google Scholar]
- Kaushik, R. Where is Negation in Merleau-Ponty’s Ontology? Res. Phenomenol. 2021, 51, 372–393. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nietzsche. Beyond Good and Evil; Kaufmann, W., Translator; Vintage: New York, NY, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Claudel, P. Art poétique; Gallimard: Paris, France, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Bradley, A. Negative Theology and Modern French Philosophy; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Barbaras, R. Desire and Distance; Milan, P.B., Translator; Stanford University Press: Stanford, CA, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. The Possibility of Philosophy; Whitmoyer, K., Translator; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Eye and Mind. In The Merleau-Ponty Aesthetics Reader: Philosophy and Painting; Johnson, G., Ed.; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1993; pp. 121–149. [Google Scholar]
- Whitmoyer, K. The Disarticulation of Time. J. Br. Soc. Phenomenol. 2015, 46, 213–232. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Husserl, E. Experience and Judgment; Churchill, J.S.; Ameriks, K., Translators; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1975. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Being and Time; Macquarrie, J.; Robinson, E., Translators; Blackwell: Oxford, UK, 1962. [Google Scholar]
- Sartre, J.-P. Nausea; Alexander, L., Translator; New Directions: New York, NY, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Sense and Non-Sense; Hubert, L.D.; Dreyfus, P.A., Translators; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1964. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Whitmoyer, K. The Primal Scream: Re-Reading the “Temporality” Chapter of Phenomenology of Perception in the Context of Negative Philosophy. Philosophies 2025, 10, 12. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10010012
Whitmoyer K. The Primal Scream: Re-Reading the “Temporality” Chapter of Phenomenology of Perception in the Context of Negative Philosophy. Philosophies. 2025; 10(1):12. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10010012
Chicago/Turabian StyleWhitmoyer, Keith. 2025. "The Primal Scream: Re-Reading the “Temporality” Chapter of Phenomenology of Perception in the Context of Negative Philosophy" Philosophies 10, no. 1: 12. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10010012
APA StyleWhitmoyer, K. (2025). The Primal Scream: Re-Reading the “Temporality” Chapter of Phenomenology of Perception in the Context of Negative Philosophy. Philosophies, 10(1), 12. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10010012