The Event Ontology of Nature
Abstract
:1. Introduction: Overcoming Ontotheology as a Transitioning into the Event Ontology of Nature
2. Nature, Life, and Interconnectedness
3. Ruyer and Simondon
4. Spacetime and Ontology
5. Organisms and Spacetime
- The living.
- The intelligent.
- The self-aware.
6. Modernism on Spacetime and the Organism: Critique and Final Remarks
7. The Event Ontology of Nature versus Pantheism
8. Conclusions
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
Appendix A. Event Ontology: A Condensed Resume
- Events are dynamical wholes.
- Space is generated by a dynamic process. (Remark. This is the crux of the emergence of the fundamental theme of ontogenesis in general, its primacy in ontology, and especially the producibility of space).
- Space is not fundamental but derivative. (Remark. First, spacetime is to be spatialized, as in Weyl’s philosophy; then, the non-fundamental character of space is invoked in order to formally establish the derivative character of spacetime itself. It should be noted that clock time in relativistic spacetime is not the same as the more primordial time of the event-as-flow. The latter is more fundamental, and is responsible of producing the derivative and less ontologically basic time of relativistic physics).
- Space is created by the collective interaction of events. (Remark. The proper concept of creation here is that of production as in Simondon’s ontogenesis. The technical content of collectivity should be captured by a topological/ontotopological approach explicating the transition from local interactions between elements, situated in the neighborhoods of each other, to the global/ontoglobal level of the whole.22).
- Each event is a manifold plus a topological flow on this manifold. (Remark. In a more careful mathematical construction of event ontology, one may show that the base manifold itself on which the evental flow is defined is redundant since the group-theoretic action generating a topological flow can be exploited to reconstruct the underlying space itself as in Lie theory or the theory of continuous groups of transformations23).
- The flow represents the wholeness of the event, its irreducible global character.
- The manifold is the matter of the event, its substrate or carrier of action. And this action is conducted via the above mentioned flow.
- The form of the event is its dynamic law, the transformation group defined on its matter (matter = the underlying phase space or the evental manifold.)
- The interaction between events is in itself analyzable into form and matter:
- (a)
- The matter component is the interpenetration between the two underlying manifolds of the interacting events.
- (b)
- The form component is the topological compatibility condition between the flows of the two events existing in this overlapping region.
- Space results from the overall pattern of interactions among all events. The formal structure of this pattern is nothing but the conditions of topological/ontotopological compatibility mentioned above.
- Space is an emergent phenomenon (the emergent character of space, time, and spacetime has been rediscovered recently in quantum gravity24).
- There is a bifurcation of the being-with mode of Being’s togetherness into the following two fundamental directions, which, in turn, comport becoming toward two distinguishable chaotic attractor states:
- (a)
- The macroscopic dimension of the world (the molar level): Space.
- (b)
- The microscopic dimension of the world (the molecular level): Events.
- As a produced molar ontological macro-level of experience, space is linked to the chaotic attractor of the machinic assemblage of organization. This is a zone organically connected to actuality. On the molecular level, however, the chaotic attractor is linked to the intensive microfields associated with events and their assemblages. This is a zone intimately connected to virtuality.25
- The global structure of reality is space at large. The local structure of reality is precisely that ontotopological order determined by the collective pattern of interactions (via conditions of topological compatibility) between the constituting events.
- The fundamental problem of ontology is to understand the essence of the interrelationship between the local and global.
- The mystery of metaphysics is the reciprocal interdependence of the whole on the part and the part on the whole. The crux of this relationship, as was envisaged correctly by Aristotle, Leibniz, Russell, and Heidegger, is topological in essence. We prefer the enlarged term ontotopological.
- The ontological expansion of space (ontospace) is the bridge between mind and nature. The gulf between idealism and materialism is to be closed by adopting the Mach-, Russell-, Whitehead-inspired metaphysical program of seeing elemental events as the ultimate fundamental constitutive bases of reality.
- In such an approach, ontospace would assume the hidden form of a subtle “aspect of nature” that is still yet to be revealed to the essentially redundant “human intellect”, though such “revelation” would occur mainly through nonlogical mathematical abductive thinking and creative nonpersonal artistic imagination.
- In event ontology, we don’t aim at blocking the way to introspection and phenomenological research, but encourage a revival of materialistic thinking that is more abstract and formalistic than many idealist positions, but without falling into the trap of erecting a global Cartesian or transcendental Subject. This is an approach that we propose to call abstract materialism, which we see as a continuation of ancient modes of thinking, such as those of the pre-Socratic Ionian physiologists, the Stoics, and the Epicureans.
- Although we describe space as “constructed”, it is not our intention to claim that the naturalistic creative process is governed by a mental power. Nor that Nature is enveloped by Nous. The creative process is not even an intellectual principle. We remain agnostic with regard to the ultimate prime dynamic agent lurking behind creativity in Nature.
- Events are not fictitious nominal placeholders like points and numbers, but essential ontological elements. Understanding their ‘being’ is the major field of investigation conducted by Heidegger. In the present work, we focus on formal ontology within the context of mathematical philosophy and nature philosophy, following the tradition of Russell, Whitehead, and Deleuze. The work of Heidegger is implicitly presupposed everywhere. It permeates every tangible 21st-century philosophy, or even beyond.
- The event’s matter is not fundamental (against substance ontology). Form is essential being. Since the form of events is the topological dynamic flow, it is conceivable that the evental manifold (matter) may be dispensed with and hence an event can be given only in terms of its dynamical law. But flow is a kind of relation (in fact, a continuum of relations with a topological structure.) Thus, an event is actually a pure relation, and the ultimate stuff of reality is relations.
- Pure relations as the ontological building blocks of reality. A pure relation is a relation free of its relata (fulfilment of Leibniz’s, Russell’s, Simondon’s, and Deleuze’s programmatic dreams26).
Appendix B. Remarks on the Historical and Conceptual Construction of Event Ontology
- Leibniz’s Monadology [72] is probably the first systematic event ontology we are aware of. However, Leibniz’s monad has very little in common with the modern concept of the event described above. Nevertheless, the famous Leibnizian “self-perception” trait of the monad might be interpreted as a form of internal ontotopological flow.
- On the ontogenesis of space in event ontology, see Russell [84,86,125] and Whitehead [57,77,105]. Auyang’s ontology could be considered another more recent example illustrating how spacetime can be generated from a larger cluster of interacting agents [11]. However, note that Auyang’s precise technical definition of the event is not the same as Russell’s and Whitehead’s or the one described in Appendix A.
- The idea of defining the event as a topological or ontotopological flow is inspired by Schelling [85] and Bergson [126,128], though they did not have the concept of the topological flow (dynamic system [246]) at their time. They grasped the event as aktions and duration, respectively. Bergson’s duration influenced Whitehead’s later work, especially Process and Reality [2]. Strangely though, Whitehead’s formal ontology, masterfully worked out in his earlier–and much shorter–text, Concept of Nature [57], does not think the event as a purely dynamic whole; instead, and like Russell [86] on this matter, Whitehead’s theory makes the event looks more like a “spacetime subdomain” (the definition of the event in Russell and Whitehead, in general, is never spelled out very clearly even in their most technically complex texts).
- Both Russell and Whitehead were misled, through their respective interpretations of Einstein’s general relativity [86,247], into defining the event as a “block of spacetime”, apparently imagining that in this manner, and following Weyl’s earlier suggestion [147,151,152], their event concept, thus defined, somehow becomes “fully dynamized”. The construction outlined in Appendix A rejects this approach, seeking instead a more radical definition of the event as a topological flow in the sense of dynamic system theory where the flow’s time is primordial and precedes all other types of time (however, the final construction would seek to somehow reformulate the topological definition in an “ontotopological” manner. Such details are outside the scope of this Appendix).
- On the other hand, we note that the formulation of event ontology outlined above may in turn suggest an alternative version based on separating time from space by defining the event as a topological flow with “external time”. However, this “external time” is neither the clock time of relativistic physics nor the thermodynamic time of cosmology [189]. It is a more primordial “evental time” which underlies all other types of time, whether physical, psychological, social, and so on.
- The term ‘ontotopology’ is proposed here in order to try to gather in a systematic manner a sorely needed subfield of “postmodern mathematics” required for the completion of the program of the event ontology of nature. In our event philosophy, the term ontotopology means topology constructed, defined, and consumed for purely ontological reason; or doing topology in and through ontology. The ontotopological is an ontological category constructed using methods borrowed from general (set-theoretic) topology. Russell [244] and Hausdorff [229] are precursors to ontotopology though they never used the term nor saw its full potential.
- The concept of topological compatibility conditions is inspired by Guattari’s concept of “conditions of consistency” [195], which was worked out (with Deleuze) as a way to determine how a multiplicity (realized by an abstract machine as a concrete machinic assemblage) may hold its constituents together [9]. However, it does not seem to us that their ontology is an ontology of event assemblages. Their multiplicities appear to be comprised of more generic “elements” or “things”, such as particles, signs, particle-signs, molar strata, molecules, and so on. They do not operate with the technical concept of event defined as an ontotopological flow.
1 | As will be explained shortly, we believe that neither ontotheology nor the event ontology of nature (to be introduced shortly) should be viewed as ways to revive theology through ontology. However, as some of the references given in the Introduction suggest, several authors have indeed attempted to achieve precisely that goal. Our position will be that conventional theological concepts need to be either rejected or drastically revised in order to integrate them with the truly postmodernist and naturalistic position of event ontology. |
2 | A possible explanation of why the Heideggerian project of ontotheology had been negative and critical might probably be located in the fact that the prevailing modern Galilean-Cartesian science complex [28], together with the parallel and closely related social system of merchant/industrial capitalism [29], had formulated a worldview of nature through which the human dimension has been reduced to a minimal position of little importance, while the totalizing mechanization of nature and society through the machination of science and capital was allowed to reach exaggerated measures [30]. Reintroducing a form of the human that avoids falling back into Cartesianism and Idealism then required a fully-fledged destruction of the entire history of that particular brand of western metaphysics that originally lead to Descartes and Galileo. This is the path first taken by the early Heidegger [31]. On the other hand, thinkers such as Husserl sought the same goal but by in fact re-founding Cartesianism on new phenomenological foundations [32]. We reject the Husserlian approach and align ourselves instead with Heidegger’s overall path. |
3 | The key idea is that ontotheology is traditionally viewed as the critique of all ontologies of presence. It is important, however, to note that the later Heidegger rejected the very term ontology as such [30], and in fact eventually stopped using the expression being altogether. He even refused to view himself as a “philosopher”, preferring instead the epithet guide [41,42]. From this perspective, Heidegger’s negative use of ontotheology as a limitative concept came to dominate subsequent discussions of the topic. From our own view, though, it is debatable whether Heidegger’s postmytaphysical mood was able to actually overcome ontology as such. It is true that Heidegger destroyed the ontology of presence, especially the long tradition of Idealism in Western metaphysics, but that does not necessarily imply rejecting ontology as such. The standard definition of ontology given in various teaching-based lecture courses by Heidegger, which defines the field as the discourse on being-as-present [15,17,43], can or even should be enlarged in scope and expanded in content by utilizing the completely new and original ontological categories developed in Heidegger’s other texts such as Being and Time [31] and On the Event [30]. It is quite remarkable that Heidegger himself chose not to pursue this direction in his later years, preferring instead to concentrate on his rather “exotic” poetic approach to Nature based on Hölderlin [44,45]. |
4 | We will not provide detailed and complete technical definitions for each of these event-ontological concepts; only the general thrust of their generic significations will be suggested in the various sections to follow. However, see Appendices Appendix A and Appendix B for some summary technical overview. For our immediate purposes in the main text of this article, few things need to be highlighted. First, note that there is no universal agreement on the meaning or the sense alloted to each of the above mentioned terms. For instance, the ancient concept of Chaos was reexported into modernity, where it was filtered by mathematics and reshaped by science in order to be rebranded as a special, highly complex solution of nonlinear differential equations [47]. However, in later times one finds that such exotic theory of chaos-as-a-special-mathematical-solution had been considerably enlarged in scope and essence, mainly through postmodernism, where the concept was reappropriated for the purpose of constructing a more comprehensive philosophical framework encompassing wider ontological/metaphysical constructs such as chreods [48,49,50], infinite speed [51], and nature’s createdness [52]. It is in these latter expansions of the concept of Chaos where we feel more at home with respect to our proposed program of the event ontology of nature. |
5 | See Whitehead on the positive sense of the term ‘speculative’ in the philosophy of nature [74,75,76,77]. Also, he explicitly admitted the limitation of science and the need to introduce speculative elements into natural philosophy [2]. Needless to say, Whitehead’s position has been enormously influential in both physics [78] and the philosophy of nature [79]. |
6 | On the idea of ontological jurisprudence in Kant’s project, see Heidegger [17], Deleuze [80], Gadamer [81,82], and Cassirer [83]. According to some of these thinkers, negative critique in Kantian philosophy need not be non-constructive. From our perspective, it is not clear why critical philosophy should always be considered more “scientific” or “methodological” than speculative (natural) philosophy. The example of Whitehead [2] (and Russell [84]) demonstrates how one philosophy can simultaneously illuminate epistemological issues in science and be metaphysically bold and innovative (that is, “speculative” in the positive sense mentioned above). |
7 | The article itself is designed such that an appreciation of the main text might be attained without necessarily reading the Appendix. However, readers interested in learning more about event ontology may benefit from the expanded treatment given in the two Appendices and the additional references supplied therein, especially in Appendix B and also the footnotes to Appendix A. |
8 | At this stage it might be important to say few words about our choices of highlighted points of contact selected from within the past history of the philosophical movement here summoned under the programmatic banner of the “event ontology of nature”, especially in regard to our mentioning of the names of Leibniz and Schelling within this context, which may raise few eyebrows. The reader might wonder whether these two thinkers could be treated in an event-based ontological framework where the Heideggerian critique has already rejected idealism (and so did postmodernism). Since Leibniz and Schelling are sometimes linked with Idealism (Schelling more so than Leibniz), the question is whether the Leibnizian and Schellingian categories are really needed here. Our response is that when it comes to Schelling, we agree that he did advocate an early form of universal Idealism that was later famously adopted and deployed by Hegel [55]. However, it also should be borne in mind that Schelling’s main idealist texts [53] differ substantially from his more naturalistic or “materialistic” formulations found in the philosophy of nature texts [85,95]. While a Hegelian ontology of universal idealism modeled on consciousness can be linked to some formulations by Schelling [18,106,107], one cannot dismiss the latter’s other, more radical, ontologies, namely those of the event (what he called aktions [85]). In any case, it is with the second, less popular, materialist dimension of Schelling’s thought where we find a broader agreement in the event ontology of nature. Regarding Leibniz, the situation is more complicated due to the fact that his work was not fully canonized and edited by the time of his death, leading to the well-known difficulty of assessing which text is the most important or even relevant. Nevertheless, Leibniz can certainly be interpreted as a contributor to a materialist ontology of the world, in the tradition of Spinoza and more recently Althusser [108,109]. A good place to learn about this scope can be found in the texts on Leibniz by Russell [110] and Deleuze [111]. For the entire material discussed in this note, see also the different but related discussion given in Appendix B. |
9 | For more information on the technical sense in which the term ‘devolvement’ is currently understood in the ontology of nature, see Bohm’s text [122]. Roughly speaking, the paired concepts folding/unfolding could be invoked to analyze a process of “evolving/de-evolving,” where form is manifested in and through rather complex topological folding/re-folding operations. The later are busy at work, shaping nature, though to us they are mostly invisible, and are capable of both folding-in or folding-out (unfolding) while constructing or deconstructing molar strata and assemblages [111]. This concept is deeply connected with mathematical chaos [123]. In Deleuze and Guattari’s ontology, one possible interpretation of the Bohmian processes of development and devolvement (winding up and winding down) is by linking them to the processes of the deterritorialization of the Earth [9] and the de-coding of the Socius [124]. |
10 | Cf. Section 4. |
11 | |
12 | It is probably for this reason that Heidegger was not occupied with the so-called “problem of the body”. Contrary to what is mentioned sometimes in the secondary literature, Heidegger did not neglect the body but intentionally avoided emphasizing bodily aspects because he saw, correctly in our opinion, that any preoccupation with such problematic is a potential backdoor or a Trojan horse permitting the despised doctrine of Idealism to re-invade philosophy. The principal example in Heidegger’s mind is most likely Nietzsche, whose “physiological approach” to philosophy [137] Heidegger rejected as Idealism-via-Biologism [139,140]. |
13 | Cf. Appendix A. |
14 | See also Appendix B for additional information on the historical background to event ontology. |
15 | Cf. Section 7. |
16 | Cf. Section 4. |
17 | See the remarkable analysis of the subtle differences between various modes of multiplicities in Leibniz’s correspondence with Arnauld, where the ontological distinction between aggregates (a quantitative concept) and, in our terminology, assemblages or “authentic multiplicities” (a topological concept) is clearly stated [100]. Essentially the same ontological theme appears to have been picked up again by Guattari [130,195] and further developed in Deleuze and Guattari [9]. |
18 | Cf. Appendix A. |
19 | On the theory of the brain, see Deleuze’s texts on Cinema [197,198] and his last collaboration with Guattari [51]. On the ontological relation between mind and nature, see Bateson [13,14], who is fundamental for any project for the ontology of nature. In general, the relation between noology and ontology is a complex one and will not be addressed in detail here. Nevertheless, we state our opinion that noology should eventually be fully absorbed into a naturalistic ontology of an event-based framework of creativity, which, in contrast to traditional theology or Idealistic ontologies, is completely immanent and anti-transcendentalist in and through. On the concept of immanence in the philosophy of nature, see Deleuze’s late text Pure Immanence: A Life [199]. |
20 | |
21 | For a penetrating critique of the various concepts of causality found in Schopenhauer and Leibniz, see Heidegger’s texts on the principle of sufficient reason and logic [43,208]. As part of his parallel critique of Kant [15,145,146], Heidegger considered causality as an essential component of the heritage of Idealism (what he called the philosophies of presence) that dominated Western metaphysics since its First Beginning in the Greek inception of Western thinking [30,90]. In our own interpretation, the event ontology of nature as a research program antagonistic to Idealism must then reject the fundamental ontological status of causality and replace it (like spacetime) with a more primordial concept. One promising such attempt is Russell’s unorthodox concept of causality, which is closely linked to his event ontology, developed in texts such as [84,86,125], but see also Reichenbach’s interesting approach to causality in [209,210,211,212]. Both Russell and Reichenbach, now it appears to us, had developed original distinctive theories of causality that are outside conventional spacetime. For Russell, this was achieved by deploying event assemblages in order to produce spacetime itself [213], where causality is defined at the level of the events themselves, not their derivative (later) spacetime [86]. For Reichenbach, the formulation is less obvious because in that approach he moved beyond traditional spacetime proper by introducing probability spaces and purely stochastic assemblages (stochastic superspace) [210]. |
22 | See Lautman’s masterful analysis of the relation between the local and the global as reconstructed from the theory of differential equations and group theory [228]. General topology in mathematics is the principal field focused on this problem at the very abstract level of set theory [229]. Within a more “concrete” framework, the local/global dialectic can be reformulated using the language—and setting—of Lie theory [230]. These technical instructions on how to move from a local level to the more global system are fundamental for event ontology. |
23 | |
24 | |
25 | On the ontological theory of the virtual and actual, see Leibniz [72], Fichte [240], Bergson [126,127,128], Simondon [7], Ruyer [10], Whitehead [241], Deleuze [129], who don’t use the same technical terms when they refer to similar concepts. (In our opinion, Heidegger’s ontological difference [19,31] might be reinterpreted as a contribution to the ontology of virtual being, though this interpretation has not been convincingly carried out by anyone yet). The machinic-chaotic attractor construction and the molar/molecular ontology are based on Deleuze and Guattari’s model developed in the Challenger Lecture in A Thousand Plateau [9]. See in particular Murray’s original interpretation and expansion of this model [242]. |
26 | On the primacy of relations, see Russell [155,156,157,243,244], Simondon [7,8], and Deleuze [245]. The Definition of the event as a pure ontotopological flow fulfils this requirement of the primacy of relations. Note that the event’s “base manifold” can be recovered from the relational structure of the transformational law of the topological/ontotopological flow, so even the “relata” of the transformation flow group (in this case the elements of the underlying geometrical space or manifold on which the group acts) are embedded into the very structure of the relation itself. It is as if becoming begets being, an old idea in philosophy anyway though it receives an interesting independent confirmation in the mathematical philosophy and fundamental metaphysics of event ontology. |
References
- Feyerabend, P. Philosophy of Nature; Polity Press: Cambridge, UK; Medford, MA, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehead, A. Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology; Free Press: New York, NY, USA, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Heiden, G. Ontology after Ontotheology: Plurality, Event, and Contingency in Contemporary Philosophy; Duquesne University Press: Pittsburgh, PA, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Dillard, P. Non-Metaphysical Theology after Heidegger; Palgrave Macmillan US Imprint Palgrave Macmillan: New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Westphal, M. Overcoming Onto-Theology: Toward a Postmodern Christian Faith; Fordham University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Schrijvers, J. Ontotheological Turnings?: The Decentering of the Modern Subject in Recent French Phenomenology; State University of New York Press: Albany, NY, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Simondon, G. Individuation in Light of Notions of form and Information, Part I; University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Simondon, G. Individuation in Light of Notions of form and Information, Part II; University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Deleuze, G.; Guattari, F. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia; University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 1987. [Google Scholar]
- Ruyer, R. Neofinalism; University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Auyang, S. How Is Quantum Field Theory Possible; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Unger, R.; Smolin, L. The Singular Universe and the Reality of Time: A Proposal in Natural Philosophy; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Bateson, G. Steps to an Ecology of Mind; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Bateson, G. Mind and Nature: A Necessary Unity; Hampton Press: Cresskill, NJ, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. What Is a Thing? H. Regnery Co: Chicago, IL, USA, 1968. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. History of the Concept of Time: Prolegomena; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. The Basic Problems of Phenomenology; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Identity and Difference; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA; London, UK, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Basic Writings: From Being and Time (1927) to The Task of Thinking (1964); Harper Perennial Modern Thought: New York, NY, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Pathmarks; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Wolfe, J. Heidegger and Theology; Bloomsbury T & T Clark: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Wolfe, J. Heidegger’s Eschatology: Theological Horizons in Martin Heidegger’s Early Work; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Buren, J. The Young Heidegger: Rumor of the Hidden King; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Moore, I. Eckhart, Heidegger, and the Imperative of Releasement; State University of New York Press: Albany, NY, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Sweeney, C. Sacramental Presence after Heidegger: Onto-Theology, Sacraments, and the Mother’s Smile; Cascade Books: Eugene, OR, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Thomson, I. Heidegger on Ontotheology: Technology and the Politics of Education; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Feyerabend, P. Against Method; Verso: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Braudel, F. Civilization and Capitalism: 15th–18th Century (Volume 3: The Perspective of the World); University of California Press: New York, NY, USA, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Contributions to Philosophy: Of the Event; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Being and Time; HarperPerennial/Modern Thought: New York, NY, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, E. The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology: An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1970. [Google Scholar]
- Armitage, D. Heidegger’s Pauline and Lutheran Roots; Palgrave Macmillan: New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Zubiri, X. Dynamic Structure of Reality; University of Illinois Press: Urbana, IL, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Zubiri, X. On Essence; Catholic University of America Press: Washington, DC, USA, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Zubiri, X. Man and God; University Press of America: Lanham, MD, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Zubiri, X. Fundamental Problems of Western Metaphysics; University Press of America: Lanham, MD, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Zubiri, X. Nature, History, God; University Press of America: Washington, DC, USA, 1981. [Google Scholar]
- Jonas, H. The Phenomenon of Life: Toward a Philosophical Biology; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Jonas, H. The Gnostic Religion: The Message of the Alien God and the Beginnings of Christianity; Beacon Press: Boston, MA, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Country Path Conversations; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. On the Way to Language; Harper & Row: San Francisco, CA, USA, 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. The metaphysical Foundations of Logic; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Holderlin’s Hymns Germania and The Rhine; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Elucidations of Holderlin’s Poetry; Humanity Books: Amherst, NY, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Mikki, S. Homo Philosophicus: Reflections on the Nature and Function of Philosophical Thought. Philosophies 2021, 6, 77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Prigogine, I. From Being to Becoming: Time and Complexity in the Physical Sciences; W.H. Freeman: San Francisco, CA, USA, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Waddington, C.H. Strategy of the Genes; Taylor & Francis: Abingdon, UK, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Thom, R. Mathematical Models of Morphogenesis; Ellis Horwood Halsted Press: Chichester, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Thom, R. Structural Stability and Morphogenesi: An Outline of a General Theory of Models; Addison-Wesley Pub: Reading, MA, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Deleuze, G.; Guattari, F. What Is Philosophy? Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Prigogine, I.; Stengers, I. Order Out of Chaos: Man’s New Dialogue with Nature; Bantam Books: New York, NY, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Schelling, F. System of Transcendental Idealism (1800); University Press of Virginia: Charlottesville, WV, USA, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G. Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature: Being Part Two of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1830)7; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G. The Science of Logic; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, T. Summa Theologica (Complete in a Single Volume); Coyote Canyon Press: Claremont, CA, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehead, A. The Concept of Nature: The Tarner Lectures Delivered in Trinity College, November 1919; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Spinoza. Ethics; Penguin Books: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. Metaphysics; Hackett Publishing Company: Indianapolis, IN, USA; Cambridge, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Cicero, M. The Nature of the Gods; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Seneca, L. Letters on Ethics; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Seneca, L. Natural Questions; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Plotinus. The Enneads; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Proclus. The Commentaries of Proclus on the Timaeus of Plato: In Five Books, Containing a Treasury of Pythagoric and Platonic Physiology, Translated by Thomas Taylor; CreateSpace: Scotts Valley, CA, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Proclus. The Elements of Theology; Clarendon Press Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Avicenna. The Metaphysics of The Healing; Brigham Young University Press: Provo, UT, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Bloch, E. Avicenna and the Aristotelian Left; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Averroes. Averroes’ Tahafut al-Tahafut: The Incoherence of the Incoherence; Gibb Memorial Trust: London, UK, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Averroes. Averroes: On the Harmony of Religion and Philosophy; Printed for the trustees of the E.J.W. Gibb Memorial and published by Luzac: London, UK, 1961. [Google Scholar]
- Bruno, G. Cause, Principle, and Unity: Five Dialogues; Greenwood Press: Westport, CT, USA, 1976. [Google Scholar]
- Scotus, J. Philosophical Writings: A Selection; Hackett Pub. Co: Indianapolis, IN, USA, 1987. [Google Scholar]
- Leibniz, G. Philosophical Papers and Letters; D. Reidel Pub. Co: Dordrecht, Holland; Boston, MA, USA, 1976. [Google Scholar]
- Schelling, F. Bruno, or, On the Natural and the Divine Principle of Things; State University of New York Press: Albany, NY, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehead, A. Symbolism: Its Meaning and Effect; Fordham University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehead, A. The Function of Reason; Beacon Press: Boston, MA, USA, 1958. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehead, A. Adventures of Ideas; Macmillan Co: New York, NY, USA, 1933. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehead, A. Science and the Modern World; Free Press: New York, NY, USA, 1967. [Google Scholar]
- Eastman, T. (Ed.) Physics and Whitehead: Quantum, Process, and Experience; State University of New York Press: Albany, NY, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Stengers, I. Thinking with Whitehead: A Free and Wild Creation of Concepts; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA; London, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Deleuze, G. Kant’s Critical Philosophy: The Doctrine of the Faculties; University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Gadamer, H. Philosophical Hermeneutics; University of California Press: Berkeley, CA, USA, 1976. [Google Scholar]
- Gadamer, H. Truth and Method; Continuum: New York, NY, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Cassirer, E. Kant’s Life and Thought; Yale Univ. Press: New Haven, CT, USA, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, B. Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Value; Taylor & Francis: Abingdon, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Schelling, F. First Outline of a System of the Philosophy of Nature; State University of New York Press: Albany, NY, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, B. The Analysis of Matter; Spokesman: Nottingham, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Deleuze, G. Logic of Sense; Bloomsbury Academic: London, UK, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Bremen and Freiburg Lectures: Insight into That Which Is and Basic Principles of Thinking; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Cantor, G. Contributions to the Founding of the Theory of Transfinite Numbers; Dover Publications: New York, NY, USA, 1955. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Mindfulness; Continuum: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Mikki, S. Aesthetic Theory and the Philosophy of Nature. Philosophies 2021, 6, 56. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Marcuse, H. Hegel’s Ontology and the Theory of Historicity; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1987. [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, E. Logical Investigations: Volume 1; Routledge: London, UK; Taylor & Francis Group: New York, NY, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, E. Logical Investigations: Volume 2; Routledge: London, UK; Taylor & Francis Group: New York, NY, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Schelling, F. Ideas for a Philosophy of Nature as Introduction to the Study of This Science: 1797; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK; Cambridgeshire, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Humboldt, A. Views of Nature; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA; London, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Humboldt, A. Selected Writings; Alfred A. Knopf: New York, NY, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Wulf, A. The Invention of Nature: Alexander von Humboldt’s New World; Alfred A. Knopf: New York, NY, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Leibniz, G. The Labyrinth of the Continuum: Writings on the Continuum Problem, 1672–1686; Yale Univ. Press: New Haven, CT, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Leibniz, G. The Leibniz-Arnauld Correspondence: With Selections from the Correspondence with Ernst, Landgrave of Hessen-Rheinfels; Yale University Press: New Haven, CT, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Humboldt, A. Cosmos: Sketch of a Physical Description of the Universe: Volume 1; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Humboldt, A. Cosmos: Sketch of a Physical Description of the Universe: Volume 2; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Mach, E. The Analysis of Sensations, and the Relation of the Physical to the Psychical; Dover Publications: New York, NY, USA, 1959. [Google Scholar]
- Mach, E. The Science of Mechanics: A Critical and Historical Account of Its Development; Open Court: LaSalle, IL, USA, 1974. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehead, A. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge; Cosimo: New York, NY, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Hegel; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Hegel’s Concept of Experience: With a Section from Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit; Harper & Row: San Francisco, CA, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Althusser, L. The Humanist Controversy and Other Writings: 1966-67; Verso: London New York, NY, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Althusser, L. Philosophy of the Encounter: Later Writings (1978-87); Verso: London New York, NY, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, B. A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz; Routledge: London, UK, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Deleuze, G. The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque; University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Nietzsche, F. The pre-Platonic Philosophers; University of Illinois Press: Urbana, IL, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Lovelock, J. The Vanishing Face of Gaia: A Final Warning; Basic Books: New York, NY, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Lovelock, J. The Ages of GAIA: A Biography of Our Living Earth; Norton: New York, NY, USA, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Simondon, G. On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects; Univocal Publishing, University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Scott, D. Gilbert Simondon’s Psychic and Collective Individuation: A Critical Introduction and Guide; Edinburgh University Press: Edinburgh, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Combes, M. Gilbert Simondon and the Philosophy of the Transindividual; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Mills, S. Gilbert Simondon: Information, Technology, and Media; Rowman & Littlefield International: London, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Bardin, A. Epistemology and Political Philosophy in Gilbert Simondon: Individuation, Technics, Social Systems; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Boever, A.; Murray, S.S.Y.; Roffe, J. (Eds.) Gilbert Simondon: Being and Technology; Edinburgh University Press: Edinburgh, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Ruyer, R. The Genesis of Living Forms; Rowman & Littlefield Publishers: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Bohm, D. Wholeness and the Implicate Order; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Gilmore, R. The Topology of Chaos: Alice in Stretch and Squeezeland; Wiley-VCH John Wiley distributor: Weinheim, Germany; Chichester, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Deleuze, G.; Guattari, F. Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia; University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, B. Our Knowledge of the External world: As a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Bergson, H. Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness; Harpars: New York, NY, USA, 1960. [Google Scholar]
- Bergson, H. Matter and Memory; Zone Books: New York, NY, USA, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Bergson, H. Creative Evolution; University Press of America: Lanham, MD, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Deleuze, G. Difference and Repetition; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Guattari, F. The Machinic Unconscious: Essays in Schizoanalysis; Semiotext(e) Distributed by the MIT Press: Los Angeles, CA, USA; Cambridge, MA, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Guattari, F. Schizoanalytic Cartographies; Bloomsbury: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Dosse, F. Gilles Deleuze & Felix Guattari: Intersecting Lives; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Bifo, F. Flix Guattari: Thought, Friendship, and Visionary Cartography; Palgrave Macmillan: London, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Deleuze, G. Bergsonism; Zone Books: New York, NY, USA, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Roffe, J. Deleuze’s Philosophical Lineage I; Edinburgh University Press: Edinburgh, UK, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Nietzsche, F. The Will to Power: Selections from the Notebooks of the 1880s; Penguin classics, Penguin Books: London, UK, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Nietzsche, F. The Will to Power; Random House: New York, NY, USA, 1967. [Google Scholar]
- Nietzsche, F. Writings from the late Notebooks; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Nietzsche: Volumes 1 and 2 (Volume 1: The Will to Power as Art, Volume 2: The Eternal Recurrence of the Same); HarperSanFrancisco: San Francisco, CA, USA, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Nietzsche: Volumes 3 and 4 (Volume 3: The Will to Power as Knowledge and as Metaphysics; Volume 4: Nihilism); HarperSanFrancisco: San Francisco, CA, USA, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Descartes, R. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes: Volume 1; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Descartes, R. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes: Volume 2; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Descartes, R. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes: Volume 3 (The Correspondence); Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Grosz, E. The Incorporeal: Ontology, Ethics, and the Limits of Materialism; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 1962. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. The Question Concerning the Thing: On Kant’s Doctrine of the Transcendental Principles; Rowman & Littlefield International Ltd.: London Lanham, MD, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Weyl, H. Space, Time, Matter; Dover Publications: New York, NY, USA, 1952. [Google Scholar]
- Descartes, R. Discourse on Method, Optics, Geometry, and Meteorology; Hackett Pub: Indianapolis, IN, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Einstein, A. Ideas and Opinions; Crown Trade Paperbacks: New York, NY, USA, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Pesic, P. (Ed.) Beyond Geometry: Classic Papers from Riemann to Einstein; Dover Publications: Mineola, NY, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Weyl, H. Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Weyl, H. Mind and Nature: Selected Writings on Philosophy, Mathematics, and Physics; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Epperson, M. Foundations of Relational Realism: A Topological Approach to Quantum Mechanics and the Philosophy of Nature; Lexington Books: Lanham, MD, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Malpas, J. Heidegger’s Topology: Being, Place, World; MIT: Cambridge, MA, USA; London, UK, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, B. The Principles of Mathematics; W.W. Norton: New York, NY, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, B. Collected Writings, Volume III: Toward the Principles of Mathematics: 1900-02; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehead, A.; Russell, B. Principia Mathematica: Volume I; Rough Draft Printing: San Bernardio, CA, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehead, A.; Russell, B. Principia Mathematica: Volume II; Rough Draft Printing: San Bernardio, CA, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehead, A.; Russell, B. Principia Mathematica: Volume III; Rough Draft Printing: San Bernardio, CA, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. Timaeus and Critias; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Barbour, J. The Discovery of Dynamics: A Study from a Machian Point of View of the Discovery and the Structure of Dynamical Theories; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, B. My philosophical Development; Spokesman: Nottingham, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Badiou, A. Being and Event; Bloomsbury Academic: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Bohm, D. Quantum Theory; Dover Publications: New York, NY, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Bohm, D. The Undivided Universe: An Ontological Interpretation of Quantum Theory; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Epperson, M. Quantum Mechanics and the Philosophy of Alfred North Whitehead; Fordham University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Reichenbach, H. From Copernicus to Einstein; Read Books Ltd.: Redditch, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Heisenberg, W. Physics and Philosophy: The Revolution in Modern Science; HarperPerennial: New York, NY, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Wheeler, J. Geons, Black Holes, and Quantum Foam: A Life in Physics; Norton: New York, NY, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Rovelli, C. Reality Is Not What it Seems: The Journey to Quantum Gravity; Riverhead Books: New York, NY, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Shimony, A. Search for a Naturalistic World View, Volume I; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Shimony, A. Search for a Naturalistic World View, Volume II; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Omnes, R. Quantum Philosophy: Understanding and Interpreting Contemporary Science; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Schelling, F. The Philosophy of Art; University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Schelling, F. The Ages of the World; State University of New York Press: Albany, NY, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Penrose, R. The Road to Reality: A Complete Guide to the Laws of the Universe; Vintage Books: New York, NY, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Monod, J. Chance and Necessity: An Essay on the National Philosophy of Modern Biology; Fontana: London, UK, 1974. [Google Scholar]
- Jacob, F. The Logic of Life: A History of Heredity; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Darwin, C. The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection; Barnes & Noble Classics: New York, NY, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Gould, S. The Structure of Evolutionary Theory; Belknap Press of Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Gould, S. Wonderful Life: The Burgess Shale and the Nature of History; W.W. Norton & Company: New York, NY, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Dawkins, R. The Selfish Gene; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Hoffmeyer, J. Biosemiotics: An Examination into the Signs of Life and the Life of Signs; University of Scranton Press: Scranton, PA, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Zhegunov, G. The Dual Nature of Life: Interplay of the Individual and the Genome; Springer: Berlin, Germany; New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Ward, P. Lamarck’s Revenge: How Epigenetics Is Revolutionizing Our Understanding of Evolution’s Past and Present; Bloomsbury Publishing, Inc.: New York, NY, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Baedke, J. Above the Gene, Beyond Biology: Toward a Philosophy of Epigenetics; University of Pittsburgh Press: Pittsburgh, PA, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Peterson, E. The Life Organic: The Theoretical Biology Club and the Roots of Epigenetics; University of Pittsburgh Press: Pittsburgh, PA, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Petkov, V. Relativity and the Nature of Spacetime; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands; New York, NY, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Mikki, S. On the Direction of Time: From Reichenbach to Prigogine and Penrose. Philosophies 2021, 6, 79. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schopenhauer, A. The World as Will and Representation, Volume 1; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Schopenhauer, A. The World as Will and Representation, Volume 2; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Jung, C.G. The Archetypes and the Collective Unconscious; Routledge: London, UK, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Hartmann, E. Philosophy of the Unconscious: Speculative Results According to the Inductive Method of Physical; Routledge: London, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Lucretius. The Nature of Things; Norton: New York, NY, USA, 1977. [Google Scholar]
- Guattari, F. The Anti-Oedipus Papers; Semiotext(e) Distributed by MIT Press: New York, NY, USA; Cambridge, MA, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Uexkull, J. A Foray Into the Worlds of Animals and Humans: With A Theory of Meaning; University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Deleuze, G. Cinema 1: The Movement-Image; University of Minnesota: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 1986. [Google Scholar]
- Deleuze, G. Cinema 2: The Time-Image; University of Minnesota: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 1986. [Google Scholar]
- Deleuze, G. Pure Immanence: Essays on a Life; Zone Books Distributed by the MIT Press: New York, NY, USA; Cambridge, MA, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Lorenz, K. The Natural Science of the Human Species: An Introduction to Comparative Behavioral Research, the Russian Manuscript (1944–1948); MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Kauffman, S. The Origins of Order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Smolin, L. The Life of the Cosmos; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. The Question Concerning Technology, and Other Essays; HarperCollins Publishers: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Maxwell, J. Maxwell on Molecules and Gases; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1986. [Google Scholar]
- Boltzmann, L. Theoretical Physics and Philosophical Problems: Selected Writings; Reidel Pub. Co: Dordrecht, The Netherlands; Boston, MA, USA, 1974. [Google Scholar]
- Cassirer, E. Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics: Historical and Systematic Studies of the Problem of Causality; Yale University Press: New Haven, CT, USA, 1956. [Google Scholar]
- Lacan, J. Ecrits: The First Complete Edition in English; Norton: New York, NY, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. The Principle of Reason; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Reichenbach, H. The Philosophy of Space & Time; Dover Publications: New York, NY, USA, 1958. [Google Scholar]
- Reichenbach, H. The Direction of Time; Dover: Mineola, NY, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Reichenbach, H. Selected Writings: Volume I; D. Reidel Pub. Co: Dordrecht, The Netherland, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Reichenbach, H. Selected Writings: Volume II; D. Reidel Pub. Co: Dordrecht, The Netherland, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Mikki, S. On Russell’s 1927 Book The Analysis of Matter. Philosophies 2021, 6, 40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Newton, I. Isaac Newton: Philosophical Writings; Cambridge University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Fanning, P. Isaac Newton and the Transmutation of Alchemy: An Alternate View of the Scientific Revolution; North Atlantic Books: Berkeley, CA, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Einstein, A.; Infeld, L. The Evolution of Physics: From Early Concepts to Relativity and Quanta; Simon and Schuster: New York, NY, USA, 1966. [Google Scholar]
- Eddington, A. The Nature of the Physical World (The Gifford Lectures: 1927); Books on Demand: Norderstedt, Germany, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, I. Critique of Pure Reason; Dover Publications: Mineola, NY, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, I. Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, E. Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy; M. Nijhoff Distributors: Boston, MA, USA, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Graham, D. The Texts of Early Greek Philosophy: The Complete Fragments and Selected Testimonies of the Major Presocratics; Cambridge University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Laertius, D. Lives of the Eminent Philosophers; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Karatani, K. Isonomia and the Origins of Philosophy; Duke University Press: Durham, UK, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Schelling, F. Philosophy of Revelation (1841-42): And Related Texts; Spring Publications: Thompson, CT, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehead, A. Modes of Thought; Free Press: New York, NY, USA, 1968. [Google Scholar]
- Jung, C.G. Psychology and Religion: The Collected Works of C.G. Jung, Volume 11; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1975. [Google Scholar]
- Mitchell, A. The Fourfold: Reading the Late Heidegger; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Lautman, A. Mathematics, Ideas, and the Physical Real; Continuum: New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Hausdorff, F. Set Theory; American Mathematical Society: Providence, RI, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Pontryagin, L.S. Topological Groups; Gordon and Breach Science Publishers: New York, NY, USA, 1986. [Google Scholar]
- DeLanda, M. Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy; Bloomsbury: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Lie, S. Theory of Transformation Groups I; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Godement, R. Introduction to the Theory of Lie Groups; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Montgomery, D.; Zippin, L. Topological Transformation Groups; Dover Publications, Inc.: Mineola, NY, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Ellis, R. Lectures on Topological Dynamics; W.A. Benjamin: New York, NY, USA, 1969. [Google Scholar]
- Gottschalk, W.; Hedlund, G.A. Topological Dynamics; American Mathematical Society: Providence, RI, USA, 1955. [Google Scholar]
- Akin, E. Recurrence in Topological Dynamics: Furstenberg Families and Ellis Actions; Plenum Press: New York, NY, USA, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Rovelli, C. Quantum Gravity; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Rovelli, C. Covariant loop Quantum Gravity: An Elementary Introduction to Quantum Gravity and Spinfoam Theory; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Fichte, J. Foundations of Transcendental Philosophy (Wissenschaftslehre) nova Methodo (1796/99); Cornell University Press: Ithaca, NY, USA, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehead, A. Science and Philosophy; Philosophical Library: New York, NY, USA, 1974. [Google Scholar]
- Murray, J. Deleuze & Guattari: Emergent Law; Routledge: Oxfordshire, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, B. The Philosophy of Logical Atomism; Open Court: LaSalle, IL, USA, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, B. Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy; Barnes & Noble: New York, NY, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Deleuze, G. Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay on Hume’s Theory of Human Nature; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Sell, G. Topological Dynamics and Ordinary Differential Equations; Van Nostrand-Reinhold: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1971. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehead, A. The Principle of Relativity; Cosimo Classics: New York, NY, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2021 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Mikki, S. The Event Ontology of Nature. Philosophies 2021, 6, 88. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies6040088
Mikki S. The Event Ontology of Nature. Philosophies. 2021; 6(4):88. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies6040088
Chicago/Turabian StyleMikki, Said. 2021. "The Event Ontology of Nature" Philosophies 6, no. 4: 88. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies6040088
APA StyleMikki, S. (2021). The Event Ontology of Nature. Philosophies, 6(4), 88. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies6040088