Kierkegaard’s Descriptive Philosophy of Religion: The Imagination Poised between Possibility and Actuality
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Results
2.1. Kierkegaard on Imagination and Philosophical Description: A Sketch
The self is reflection, and the imagination is reflection, is the rendition of the self as the self’s possibility. The imagination is the possibility of any and all reflection, and the intensity of this medium is the possibility of the intensity of the self.([15] p. 31)
- So central is the imagination as the source of “possibility” to Kierkegaard’s concept of the religious and of specifically Christian existence that in The Sickness Unto Death, Anti-Climacus famously states that when “the ingeniousness of the human imagination” can no longer create possibility, “then only this helps: that for God everything is possible” ([15] pp. 38–40, p. 39).
2.1.1. Descriptive Ontology
There is an old proverb: oratio, tentatio, meditatio faciunt theologum [prayer, trial, meditation make a theologian]. Similarly, for a subjective thinker, imagination, feeling, and dialectics in impassioned existence-inwardness are required. But first and last, passion.([19] I, p. 350)
2.1.2. Pluralist Epistemology
Scientific scholarship orders the elements of subjectivity within a knowledge about them … [that] is an annulment of, a removal from existence. In existence this does not hold true. If thinking makes light of imagination, then imagination in turn makes light of thinking, and the same with feeling. The task is not to elevate the one at the expense of the other, but the task is equality, contemporaneity, and the medium in which they are united is existing.([19] I, pp. 347–348, original italics)
To exist is an art. The subjective thinker is esthetic enough for his life to have esthetic content, ethical enough to regulate it, dialectical enough in thinking to master it.
- That artistry is the subjective thinker’s task: “to understand himself in existence”([19] I, p. 351, original italics).
His form must first and last be related to existence, and in this regard he must have at his disposal the poetic, the ethical, the dialectical, the religious.([19] I, p. 357)
- As a thinker, she relates abstract thought to herself. Ethically, the subjective thinker does not admire others but attends to the ethical as a personal requirement, not in the “form of actuality”, that is, as already realized, but in the “form of possibility”, for “then whether or not the reader wants to exist in it is placed as close as possible to him” as a requirement ([19] I, pp. 358–359, p. 359). So, too, religiously, the subjective thinker does not admire a religious prototype like Job: “that Job believed should be presented in such a way that for me it comes to mean whether I too, will have faith” ([19] I, p. 359). In short, the movement at the heart of the subjective thinker is one of passionate interest in moving from imagined possibilities to actuality in one’s own existence. This is at the heart of Kierkegaard’s refashioning of a pluralist epistemology, oriented cognitively not only to objective knowledge but to the passional “subjective knowledge” found in ethics and religion.
2.1.3. Poetry as Investigative Tool
Aristotle remarks in his Poetics that poetry is superior to history, because history presents only what has occurred, poetry what could and ought to have occurred, i.e., poetry has possibility at its disposal. Possibility, poetic and intellectual, is superior to actuality; the esthetic and the intellectual are disinterested. But there is only one interest, the interest in existing; disinterestedness is the expression for indifference to actuality.
- In this passage, Kierkegaard reflects, too, the Kantian and Romantic conceptions of the poetic as “disinterested”, and a few pages earlier, Climacus writes the following:
Poetry and art have been called an anticipation of the eternal. If one wants to call them that, one must nevertheless be aware that poetry and art are not essentially related to an existing person, since the contemplation of poetry and art, “joy over the beautiful”, is disinterested, and the observer is contemplatively outside himself qua existing person.
- Yet Climacus agrees with Aristotle that “poetry is superior to history”, or as Aristotle puts it in Poetics, “poetry is something more philosophic and of graver import than history, since its statements are of the nature rather of universals, whereas those of history are singulars”([19] II, p. 246n535, quoting, again, Aristotle’s Poetics).
2.1.4. Observer Figures and Imaginary Constructing
- 1.
- Kierkegaard uses “imaginary constructions” to fuse dialectic and poetic features of philosophical thought by attending to particular characters: a central tool for his goal of a descriptive philosophy capable of exploring subjective existence.
- 2.
- Imaginative constructions enable the descriptive philosopher of subjective thinking to explore the immense differences, indeed, breaches within ethical and religious existence, the particular features of ethics, of “immanent” religiosity, and forms of religion that break the mold of immanent religion. This is accomplished primarily by how various observed “figures” or “characters” embody the passional qualifications appropriate to each. A central motif of many of these figures is their struggle. Abraham in Fear and Trembling is, of course, a prime example, as his devotion to God and his love for Isaac are tested in the command to sacrifice the child of promise, a breach with the ethical and a situation incommunicable to anyone else.
- 3.
- These observer figures, employing imaginative constructions alert to religious particularities, embody epistemic humility. They are keenly aware of what they can understand and cannot understand in the figures they observe. A prime example is Johannes de Silentio, the author of Fear and Trembling. He explores Abraham with all the force of his dialectical imagination, but finally, “Abraham I cannot understand”, for Abraham’s “movement of faith must continually be made by virtue of the absurd, but yet in such a way, please note, that one does not lose the finite but gains it whole and intact” ([26], p. 37). Silentio, himself “by no means a philosopher”, says that he will not attempt to “go further than faith” but stands “amazed” before Abraham ([26] pp. 7, 23, 27). In a marvelous image, Silentio writes
I presumably can describe the movements of faith, but I cannot make them. In learning to go through the motions of swimming, one can be suspended from the ceiling in a harness and then presumably describe the movements, but one is not swimming.([26] pp. 37–38, italics added)
- 4.
- These observer figures and imaginary constructors, even with their epistemic humility, are still confident that religious existence is philosophically “mappable”, understandable “from the outside”, and that one need not be a believer to understand religion. With regard to Christianity specifically, Climacus affirms that it can be described to someone; a pagan philosopher, for example, can be “told what Christianity is so that he could choose” ([19] I, p. 372).
That one can know what Christianity is without being a Christian must, then, be answered in the affirmative. Whether one can know what it is to be a Christian without being one is something else, and it must be answered in the negative.
- The distinction between a descriptive conceptual understanding and the understanding available from participation, in this case, “knowing what Christianity is” and “knowing what it is to be a Christian”, is central to the method of Kierkegaard’s descriptive philosophy of ethical and religious possibilities. The observer is in a position to give highly detailed “imaginative constructive” accounts of such possibilities yet can also account for the experience of reaching limits in not understanding what it is “to be” a Christian. The two are not mutually exclusive14.
- 5.
- “Imaginary constructing” is, finally, central to “indirect communication”. We have seen how Kierkegaard’s “imaginative constructions” serve several important functions in his descriptive philosophy, fusing dialectic and poetic features of philosophic thought by creating particular characters, clarifying differences within ethical and religious existence, enabling the epistemic humility of the philosopher when confronting those imagined possibilities, yet at the end enabling a firm confidence that descriptive philosophy “from the outside” is possible. Now Climacus adds a further point concerning how the imaginative construction in Repetition relates reader with author, insisting that it
establishes a chasmic gap between reader and author and fixes the separation of inwardness between them, so that a direct understanding is made impossible. The imaginary construction is the conscious, teasing revocation of the communication, which is always of importance to an existing person who writes for existing persons, lest the relation be changed to that of a rote reciter who writes for rote reciters.([19] I, pp. 263–264)
- Climacus, describing the “imaginary psychological construction [psychologisk Experiment]” in Repetition, reveals well how this “chasmic gap” preserves the “inwardness” of reader and author:
If what is said is earnestness to the writer, he keeps the earnestness essentially to himself. If the recipient interprets it as earnestness, he does it essentially by himself, and precisely this is the earnestness. … The being-in-between [Mellemværende] of the imaginary construction encourages the inwardness of the two away from each other in inwardness.([19] I, p. 264, original italics)
- Imaginative constructions, finally, present a challenge to both the author and the reader, for each is individually responsible for how they might (or might not) engage with the imaginary construction.
2.1.5. Summary
2.2. Kierkegaard’s Challenge to Contemporary Philosophy of Religion: Beyond Descriptive Objectivism
2.2.1. Climacus and Ancient Philosophy
With regard to the essential truth, a direct relation between spirit and spirit is unthinkable … Socrates was a teacher of the ethical, but he was aware that there is no direct relation between the teacher and the learner because inwardness is truth, and inwardness in the two is precisely the path away from each other.
- For Climacus, and Kierkegaard, the “Greeks” represent the primary model for challenging modern philosophical objectivism, calling philosophy back, through the use of imaginary construction as indirect communication, to a concern with the existing individual and the cultivation of “essential knowing” and “inwardness”.
2.2.2. Communicating “Subjective Thinking”
what if this entire undertaking [of establishing the truth of Christianity “from a speculative point of view”] were a chimera, what if it could not be done; what if Christianity is indeed subjectivity, is inward deepening, that is, what if only two kinds of people can know something about it: those who are impassionedly, infinitely interested in their eternal happiness and in faith build this happiness on their faith-bound relation to it, and those who with the opposite passion (yet with passion) reject it—the happy and the unhappy lovers?([19] I, p. 52)
Simply stated: How can I, Johannes Climacus, share in the happiness that Christianity promised? The issue pertains to me alone, partly because, if properly presented, it will pertain to everyone in the same way.([19] I, p. 17)
- Climacus’s rhetorical stance as a “subjective author” attacks objectivism by inviting his reader to entertain, at least imaginatively, a shift in perspective, directing attention to the question of passion; indeed, his strategies seek to evoke passion. Climacus, as a philosopher, unites description with indirect communication, seeking to undercut the pretensions of objectivist “speculative thought”. These multiple strategies, despite appearances, are not at odds but are two sides of the one philosophical and poetic endeavor.
Like Plato in the Gorgias, Kierkegaard also presents contrasting views of life; but unlike Plato, who uses Socrates as the ethical representative to conquer each of his antagonists by superior argumentative skill, Kierkegaard refuses to allow a philosophical victory for even the view of life he espouses. Philosophy remains descriptive and neutral.([31] p. 19, original italics)
- Philosophically and theologically, this is an important interpretative point in approaching Kierkegaard’s writings since he is so often portrayed as, for example, “a Christian existentialist”. Even if, as Holmer implies, he does himself espouse Christianity, he always presents the Christian faith as one point of view among several, and in that sense, philosophy remains “descriptive and neutral”. But “neutral” is not “indifferent”, and Kierkegaard presents the passion of Christian faith in relation to other passionate stances, allowing the reader to make up her own mind.
It does not depend, then, merely upon what one sees but what one sees depends upon how one sees; all observation is not just a receiving, a discovering, but also a bringing forth, and insofar as it is that, how the observer himself is constituted is indeed decisive. When one person sees one thing and another sees something else in the same thing, then the one discovers what the other conceals.([36] p. 59; cf. p. 208)
- “How one sees” another person, Kierkegaard continues, points to “a person’s inner being” ([36] p. 60).
2.2.3. Afterword: Kierkegaard and Hadot
Rousseau, Shaftesbury, Schopenhauer, Emerson, Thoreau, Kierkegaard, Marx, Nietzsche, William James, Bergson, Wittgenstein, Merleau-Ponty, and still others. All, in one way or another, were influenced by the model of ancient philosophy, and conceived of philosophy not only as a concrete, practical activity but also as a transformation of our way of inhabiting and perceiving the world.
- Hadot’s quest to restore the spirit of ancient Greek philosophy illuminates Kierkegaard’s own attempt to create a descriptive philosophy that goes beyond theoretical disinterestedness to nurturing personal formation and places Kierkegaard’s work in a broader perspective that continues to challenge the professionalization of contemporary philosophy of religion to this day.
3. Discussion
4. Materials and Methods
- 1.
- Placing Kierkegaard’s thought historically within the context of natural theology, rationalism, and speculative thought in order to describe central features of his new understanding of a descriptive philosophy of religion.
- 2.
- Close reading of Kierkegaard’s texts, in discussion with other scholars, focusing upon his concept of the imagination in a descriptive ontology of human existence, a pluralist epistemology, poetry as investigative tool, and the use of observer figures and imaginative constructing. Rather than resulting, however, in a philosophical “objectivism”, Kierkegaard’s engagement with the Greek philosophical tradition, as well as his conceptual and poetic investigations of the “passions” of “subjective thinking”, aim at imaginatively eliciting in the reader at least the possibility of new passions, always by means of indirect communication. Kierkegaard’s descriptive philosophy, therefore, remains a challenge to modern “objectivist” philosophy of ethics and religion.
- 3.
- A comparative reading of Kierkegaard’s enthusiasm for “the Greek principle” in philosophy with Pierre Hadot’s historical recovery and championing of ancient philosophy as a “way of life”.
- 4.
- A constructive proposal regarding Kierkegaard’s descriptive philosophy of religion in relation to particular religious traditions, especially Christianity, but also how his descriptive philosophy can engage religious traditions beyond Christianity.
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | See Furtak [4] pp. 94, 98. Furtak rightly notes that not all of these features can, of course, be attributed to every thinker from Descartes to Hegel, but “there is … a cluster of assumptions which bear a family resemblance to each other and which do more or less define the modern epistemological tradition” ([4] p. 99, original italics). |
2 | Literature on Kierkegaard’s concept of the imagination (Indbildningskraft or Phantasi[e]), and related topics, is extensive and growing. The following list is not exhaustive: Gouwens [5]; Ferreira [6]; the essays in a special issue on the topic “Imagination in Kierkegaard and Beyond”, edited by Kaftanski [7]. The imagination is relevant to recent accounts of selfhood and identity, especially narrative identity, including Davenport [8]; Rudd [9]; Stokes [10,11]. Helms [12,13,14] is making significant contributions to the theme of imagination. |
3 | See Evans [16] pp. 64–65 on the appropriateness of the phrase “descriptive ontology”. |
4 | While The Sickness Unto Death famously echoes Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, Roe Fremstedal [17] argues for the important influence of Kant on the philosophical and theological anthropology in Kierkegaard’s work, for both thinkers, first, sketch “a normative non-naturalistic anthropology that includes teleology, ethics, and religion”, and second, “both emphasize what is common to all humans”. Most importantly for our purposes on the theme of the imagination, “Both are concerned with human actuality, possibilities, and (objective) ideals”. “For Kierkegaard, the past seems to represent the actual, the future the possibilities, and the present the moment in which the self relates to the whole by taking full responsibility for itself” (citing Stokes [11] p. 163). But Kierkegaard moves beyond Kant “particularly by introducing the concept of facticity and richer notions of historicity and selfhood”, “anticipating twentieth-century phenomenology and existentialism” ([17] p. 327). With this influence from Kant, Kierkegaard thus marks a watershed in descriptive accounts of “what it means to be an embodied human being and to become a self” ([17] p. 320). As we will see, however, Kierkegaard moves even further beyond Kant in another obvious yet crucial way: his remarkable strategies of using poetry as an investigative tool. |
5 | See Kierkegaard [19] I, p. 314. Anti-Climacus in The Sickness Unto Death ([15] p. 55) speaks of a “naked abstract self” that “is the first form of the infinite self and the advancing impetus in the whole process by which a self infinitely becomes responsible for its actual self with all its difficulties and advantages”. This raises interesting interpretive issues. This could mean, as Eleanor Helms [13] describes, that there is a merely “imaginary abstract self” (John Davenport) or an “abstract self as an experienced moment of isolation that we have a duty to overcome quickly” (Patrick Stokes) ([13] p. 79). She argues rather that “an abstract self is not something that one is” ([13] p. 89). The “abstract naked self”, in Helms’s view, is abstract; it is not experienced, but is formal, transcendental in the Kantian sense ([13] p. 81), required to account for how someone can undergo change and remain itself. Helms is concerned to avoid setting up an overly simply opposition of “abstract” versus “concrete”, and also pragmatist or fideist readings of Kierkegaard that in one way or another prize the will, often the moment of will, effecting a transition from imagined possibility to concrete actuality. |
6 | See Piety [18] p. 48; “essential truth”, citing Kierkegaard [19] I, p. 199n; and “subjective truth”, citing [19] I, p. 21. It is beyond the scope of this essay to explore Piety’s discussions of “objective knowledge” and “subjective knowledge”, or of various kinds of “subjective knowledge”, including “immanent metaphysical knowledge” and “subjective knowledge of actuality”. She argues that Kierkegaard’s epistemology “is both foundationalist and nonfoundationalist, both substantive and procedural, and that it includes both internalist and externalist theories of belief justification” ([18] p. 3). She also states that “Kierkegaard’s epistemology, as [C. Stephen] Evans has observed, is both in a sense ‘premodern’ and ‘postmodern’ …. That is, it is premodern, in terms of Kierkegaard’s understanding of truth, but postmodern in its nonreductionist account of the complexities of human knowing” ([18] p. 4; citing Evans [21] p. 42). With regard to whether Kierkegaard’s understanding of subjective knowledge is realist or anti-realist, Piety argues that “knowledge that there is a God”, for example, is obtained “by allowing oneself to be immersed in the idea that there is a God”, as Kierkegaard puts it in a journal entry. But while the idea of God has reality as an idea, Kierkegaard holds further that “even though … ‘how one is oneself has an essential influence on one’s mental representation of God … he felt he was presented with religious realities that existed independently of this subjective contribution’” ([18] p. 118, quoting Martin Slotty ([22] p. 63). Crucial here, Piety argues, is that, for Kierkegaard, “the idea that there is a God is not irrelevant to the existence of the person whose idea it is” ([18] p. 119). |
7 | Kierkegaard’s extensive analysis of emotions, feelings, moods, and his crucial concept of passion has received extensive treatment by Robert C. Roberts and others. For a brief account of emotions in relation specifically to the passion of faith, and in discussion with Roberts, Frankfurt, Furtak, Nussbaum, and others, see Westphal [23], pp. 102–120. |
8 | See Kierkegaard [19] I, pp. 343–360: “The Contemporaneity of the Particular Elements of Subjectivity in the Existing Subjective Individual”, and “The Subjective Thinker: His Task, His Form, That Is, His Style”. Note again that Climacus is here describing first of all not the philosopher but rather the existing “subjective thinker”. We shall see later what this descriptive task means for the philosopher too. |
9 | On Kierkegaard’s critical redeeming of the “poetic” in existence, including religious existence, see Walsh [25]. |
10 | Citing Aristotle, Poetics, 1451 a–b; see [19] II, p. 246n535. |
11 | On the background of the concept of art as “disinterested”, see [19], II, pp. 244n522, 244–245n523, on Kant, Schiller, and H.L. Martensen. |
12 | Helms criticizes my own past “ironic” reading of Constantine in Repetition, and I concede that she sheds fresh new light on Constantine. I actually share with Helms, as I hope to make clear, the view that “imaginary constructing” in general should not be seen as “mere observation and ironic distance”, but, again, “as a tool for gaining insight and understanding”. I do however continue to see “imaginary constructing” in light also of its “poetic” associations, Kierkegaard’s critical engagement with the German Romantics, Climacus’s (and Kierkegaard’s) interests in relating “poetry as medium of the imagination” to “imaginary constructing”, and the central role of the “poetic” for Kierkegaard’s own self-understanding. |
13 | Compare [19] I, p. 272. |
14 | Evans [16] pp. 23–24 makes this point very well. |
15 | Such a descriptive approach does not avoid critiquing ethics and religion. Kierkegaard himself was a master of the hermeneutics of suspicion, witness Two Ages and his attack upon “Christendom” in The Moment. He was sympathetic as well to insights from the great critics of Christianity. Climacus praises “a scoffer who attacks Christianity and at the same time expounds it so creditably that it is a delight to read him”, likely Feuerbach ([19] I, p. 614; II, p. 270n862). |
16 | |
17 | On Kierkegaard and Socrates, see again Furtak [4]. As Furtak notes elsewhere, Climacus’s understanding of Socrates stands within the context of other thinkers Climacus finds exemplary, such as Kant and Lessing as well as Jacobi and Hamann. But Climacus holds Socrates to be the ideal superior to them all, for Socrates alone is capable of “kindling the intellectual fire that … [Climacus] is trying to light” ([27] p. 2). |
18 | Compare Kierkegaard [1] pp. 23–24. |
19 | See Stokes ([30] pp. 277–278) on Kierkegaard’s discussion of “thinking my death” in this section of Postscript in relation to the concept of “watchfulness” or “attention”. |
20 | See Furtak ([4] p. 107) for a commendable description of Climacus on death in relation to the “limits of epistemology”: “‘subjective knowledge’ is also called ‘essential knowing’” … because “not only are we quite intimately involved in these questions, but the meaning of our existence is at stake in the way that we answer them”. |
21 | See Climacus’s delightful account of how he became a philosophical author ([19] I, pp. 185–188). “Making difficulties everywhere” is at the heart of yet another rhetorical strategy Climacus employs: satire. |
22 | Barrett [29] p. 23 deals very well with both the importance of the multiplicity of voices and the variety of “life-views” in the literature. |
23 | In Kierkegaard’s overall communicative strategy, even though Socrates’s maieutic method of eliciting the truth from within is reversed in Climacus’s “Thought-Project” in Philosophical Fragments ([1] pp. 9–22) with reliance upon the “moment in time” of “the god as teacher and savior” ([1] pp. 23–36), nonetheless indirect communication, as the communication of capabilities rather than knowledge, continues to be essential throughout Kierkegaard’s literature. |
24 | |
25 | Wittgenstein [33] II, pp. 194, 206, 210, 212. Against volitionist readings of Kierkegaard on the “leap of faith”, it is important to see how transitions in Kierkegaard are not by sheer “will-power”, but by perceptual shifts in “imaginative vision”. See Ferreira [6]. As Eleanor Helms recently puts it, “Kierkegaard draws on the flexibility and changeability of the imagination, which enable imaginers to see the world in new ways … Rather than a “leap of faith” as believing without evidence (or with only practical evidence) … Kierkegaard’s leap is instead a shift in perspective motivated in part by such imaginary constructions” (Helms, [14] italics added). For a recent spirited defense of the “leap of faith” in terms of “a restricted, sophisticated, and plausible version of direct doxastic voluntarism” in contrast to “indirect doxastic voluntarism”, see Z Quanbeck [34]. (I am indebted to a reviewer for bringing this to my attention.) Helms’s emphasis on the imaginative shift in perspective, and her critique of the “leap of faith” by sheer “will-power”, need not diminish the role of conscious decision in such transitions. On this point, see, for example, Sylvia Walsh’s response to M. Jamie Ferreira on the transition to specifically Christian faith in The Sickness Unto Death. While “wholeheartedly” agreeing with the importance of the imagination, Walsh affirms too the themes of the “inversion of the will” and “faith against the understanding” ([35] p. 170n11). I suggest that light can be thrown on this matter of imagination and will by attending concretely to the importance of philosophical and theological practices, including “spiritual exercises” of exhortation and training, in using imaginative insights to, as Helms puts it, “enable imaginers to see the world in new ways”. We will return to these “spiritual exercises” in the next section. |
26 | For a good recent overview of current scholarship on “fantasy” and “imagination”, in the context of contrasts between Kierkegaard and Iris Murdoch, see Compaijen [37]. |
27 | On Socrates’s “call from ‘individual’ to ‘individual’”, Hadot says, “This is the Individual dear to Kierkegaard—the Individual as unique and unclassifiable personality” ([38] p. 30). |
28 | |
29 | Hadot [38] pp. 258–261, wherein he cites Wittgenstein as an example of a philosophical outsider. |
30 | |
31 | On Kant’s “Socratism”, which Hadot sees paralleling Kierkegaard, see Hadot [38] p. 266. Placing Kierkegaard in this company of thinkers interested in philosophy as “transformation of our way of inhabiting and perceiving the world” suggests future research into his contributions to recent interest in genre and style in the writing of philosophy more generally. (I am indebted to a reviewer for this observation.) |
32 | See Connell [42] who deals extensively with the complexity of universalistic and particularistic themes in Kierkegaard. |
References
- Kierkegaard, S. Philosophical Fragments. In Philosophical Fragments and Johannes Climacus; Hong, H.V., Hong, E.H., Eds. and Translators; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Pyper, H.S. Henrik Nicolai Clausen: The Voice of Urbane Rationalism. In Kierkegaard Research: Sources, Reception and Resources, Volume 7, Kierkegaard and His Danish Contemporaries, Tome II: Theology; Stewart, J., Ed.; Routledge: Abingdon, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2016; pp. 41–48. [Google Scholar]
- Stewart, J. Hegel’s Century: Alienation and Recognition in a Time of Revolution; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Furtak, R.A. The Kierkegaardian Ideal of ‘Essential Knowing’ and the Scandal of Modern Philosophy. In Kierkegaard’s Concluding Unscientific Postscript: A Critical Guide; Furtak, R.A., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2010; pp. 87–110. [Google Scholar]
- Gouwens, D.J. Kierkegaard’s Dialectic of the Imagination; Peter Lang: New York, NY, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Ferreira, M.J. Transforming Vision: Imagination and Will in Kierkegaardian Faith; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Kaftanski, W.T. (Ed.) History of European Ideas 2021, 47.3: Imagination in Kierkegaard and Beyond. Available online: https://journals.scholarsportal.info/browse/01916599/v47i0003 (accessed on 24 August 2023).
- Davenport, J.J. Narrative Identity, Autonomy, and Mortality: From Frankfurt and MacIntyre to Kierkegaard; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Rudd, A. Self, Value, and Narrative: A Kierkegaardian Approach; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Stokes, P. The Naked Self: Kierkegaard and Personal Identity; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Stokes, P. Kierkegaard’s Mirrors: Interest, Self, and Moral Vision; Palgrave Macmillan: New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Helms, E. Imagination and Belief. In The Kierkegaardian Mind; Buben, A., Helms, E., Stokes, P., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2019; pp. 293–304. [Google Scholar]
- Helms, E. Kierkegaard’s Metaphysics of the Self. In Kierkegaard’s The Sickness Unto Death: A Critical Guide; Hanson, J., Krishek, S., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2022; pp. 79–94. [Google Scholar]
- Helms, E. Thought Projects and Imaginary Constructions: Kierkegaard’s Experimenting Mind. 2023 Julia Watkin Spring Lecture, 4 May 2023. Title of Site: St. Olaf College, The Hong Kierkegaard Library, Lectures 2022–2023. Available online: https://www.stolaf.edu/multimedia/play/?e=4294 (accessed on 24 August 2023).
- Kierkegaard, S. The Sickness unto Death; Hong, H.V., Hong, E.H., Eds. and Translators; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Evans, C.S. Kierkegaard’s Fragments and Postscript: The Religious Philosophy of Johannes Climacus; Humanities Press International: Atlantic Highlands, NJ, USA, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Fremstedal, R. Kierkegaard’s Post-Kantian Approach to Anthropology and Selfhood. In The Kierkegaardian Mind; Buben, A., Helms, E., Stokes, P., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2019; pp. 319–330. [Google Scholar]
- Piety, M.G. Ways of Knowing: Kierkegaard’s Pluralist Epistemology; Baylor University Press: Waco, TX, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Kierkegaard, S. Concluding Unscientific Postscript to Philosophical Fragments; Hong, H.V., Hong, E.H., Eds. and Translators; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Muench, P. Kierkegaard’s Socratic Pseudonym: A Profile of Johannes Climacus. In Kierkegaard’s Concluding Unscientific Postscript: A Critical Guide; Furtak, R.A., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2010; pp. 25–44. [Google Scholar]
- Evans, C.S. Kierkegaard on Faith and the Self: Collected Essays; Baylor University Press: Waco, TX, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Slotty, M. Die Erkenntnislehre S.A. Kierkegaards. Ph.D. Thesis, Friedrich-Alexanders-Universität, Erlangen, Germany, 1915. [Google Scholar]
- Westphal, M. Kierkegaard’s Concept of Faith; William B. Eerdmans: Grand Rapids, MI, USA; Cambridge, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Evans, C.S. Passionate Reason: Making Sense of Kierkegaard’s Philosophical Fragments; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Walsh, S. Living Poetically: Kierkegaard’s Existential Aesthetics; The Pennsylvania State University Press: University Park, PA, USA, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Kierkegaard, S. Fear and Trembling. In Fear and Trembling and Repetition; Hong, H.V., Hong, E.H., Eds. and Translators; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Furtak, R.A. Introduction. In Kierkegaard’s Concluding Unscientific Postscript: A Critical Guide; Furtak, R.A., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2010; pp. 1–5. [Google Scholar]
- Kierkegaard, S. The Concept of Irony. In The Concept of Irony and Notes of Schelling’s Berlin Lectures; Hong, H.V., Hong, E.H., Eds. and Translators; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Barrett, L.C. The Passion of Kierkegaard’s Existential Method. In The Kierkegaardian Mind; Buben, A., Helms, E., Stokes, P., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2019; pp. 17–27. [Google Scholar]
- Stokes, P. Consciousness, Self, and Reflection. In The Kierkegaardian Mind; Buben, A., Helms, E., Stokes, P., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2019; pp. 269–280. [Google Scholar]
- Holmer, P.L. Kierkegaard and Philosophy. In Thinking the Faith with Passion: Selected Essays; Gouwens, D.J., Barrett, L.C., III, Eds.; Cascade Books: Eugene, OR, USA, 2012; pp. 3–23. [Google Scholar]
- Kierkegaard, S. What Is Required in Order to Look at Oneself with True Blessing in the Mirror of the Word? For Self-Examination. In For Self-Examination and Judge for Yourself! Hong, H.V., Hong, E.H., Eds. and Translators; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1990; pp. 7–51. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, L. Philosophical Investigations, 3rd ed.; Anscombe, G.E.M., Translator; Macmillan: New York, NY, USA, 1958. [Google Scholar]
- Quanbeck, Z. Resolving to Believe: Kierkegaard’s Direct Doxastic Voluntarism. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2024; early view. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Walsh, S. Living Christianly: Kierkegaard’s Dialectic of Christian Existence; The Pennsylvania State University Press: University Park, PA, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Kierkegaard, S. Eighteen Upbuilding Discourses; Hong, H.V., Hong, E.H., Eds. and Translators; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Compaijen, R. Existentialists or Mystics: Kierkegaard and Murdoch on Imagination and Fantasy in the Ethical Life. Hist. Eur. Ideas 2021, 47, 43–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hadot, P. What Is Ancient Philosophy? Chase, M., Translator; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA; London, UK, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Irina, N. Pierre Hadot: Philosophy as a Way of Life: Hadot and Kierkegaard’s Socrates. In Kierkegaard Research: Sources, Reception and Resources, Volume 11, Kierkegaard’s Influence on Philosophy, Tome II: Francophone Philosophy; Stewart, J., Ed.; Ashgate: London, UK, 2012; pp. 157–172. [Google Scholar]
- Gregor, B. The Text as Mirror: Kierkegaard and Hadot on Transformative Reading. Hist. Philos. Q. 2011, 28, 65–84. [Google Scholar]
- Sharpe, M. Socratic Ironies: Reading Hadot, Reading Kierkegaard. Sophia 2016, 55, 409–435. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Connell, G.B. Kierkegaard and the Paradox of Religious Diversity; William B. Eerdmans: Grand Rapids, MI, USA; Cambridge, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Gouwens, D.J. Kierkegaard’s Descriptive Philosophy of Religion: The Imagination Poised between Possibility and Actuality. Philosophies 2024, 9, 84. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9030084
Gouwens DJ. Kierkegaard’s Descriptive Philosophy of Religion: The Imagination Poised between Possibility and Actuality. Philosophies. 2024; 9(3):84. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9030084
Chicago/Turabian StyleGouwens, David J. 2024. "Kierkegaard’s Descriptive Philosophy of Religion: The Imagination Poised between Possibility and Actuality" Philosophies 9, no. 3: 84. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9030084
APA StyleGouwens, D. J. (2024). Kierkegaard’s Descriptive Philosophy of Religion: The Imagination Poised between Possibility and Actuality. Philosophies, 9(3), 84. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9030084