Intercorporeality, Moral Self-Development and Openness to Alterity: On Merleau-Ponty’s Redeeming of Childhood Experience
Abstract
:<<<>>> |
“But”, he continues, “does it [i.e., a philosophy of reflection] properly conceive the natal bond between me who perceives and what I perceive?” This is a crucial matter, because, as he argues, “we must reject the idea of an exterior relation between the perceiving and the perceived”. (Ibid.) The philosophies of reflection that we have inherited—grandiose systems of subjective idealism—mistakenly “assume that they can comprehend our natal bond [notre lien natal] with the world only by undoing it in order to remake it, reconstituting it, and fabricating it [in the immanence of subjectivity]”. (Ibid.) Consequently, Merleau-Ponty will argue that “It is a question not of putting our perceptual faith in place of reflection, but on the contrary, a question of taking into account the total situation, which involves reference from the one to the other”. Thus, as he states, “We have to situate the relation [between myself and the perceived object] within a more muted relationship with the world, that is to say, within an initiation into the world upon which it rests and which is always already accomplished when the reflective return intervenes”. (VI 35). He adds, however, that “we will miss that relationship—which we shall call here our openness upon the world [ouverture au monde]—the moment that [we depend solely on] the reflective effort to capture it”. (VI 35).What will always make of the philosophy of reflection not only a temptation but a route that must be followed is that it is true in what it denies, that is, the exteriority of the relation between a world in itself and myself, conceived as a process of the same type as those that unfold within the world—whether one imagines an intrusion of the world in myself, or, on the contrary, some excursion of my look among the things of the world.(VI 32)
<<<>>> |
<<<>>> |
- To say more than human things with human voice,
- That cannot be; to say human things with more
- Than human voice, that, also, cannot be;
- To speak humanly from the height or from the depth
- Of human things, that is acutest speech.
In the last years of his life, Merleau-Ponty interpreted this universality in terms of the metaphor of flesh, challenging the extreme idealism in systems of thought for which what unifies everything is the mind. More on his strange notion of flesh is still to come.It is in our present that true history obtains the force to refer everything else to the present. The other whom I respect receives his life from me as I receive my life from him. A philosophy of history does not deprive me of any rights and privileges. It simply adds to my personal obligations the obligation to understand situations other than my own and to create a path between my life and the life of others. But the lines between one life and another are not traced in advance. It is through the action of culture that I come to abide in lives that are not mine. I confront them, I reveal them to one another. I make them share equally in an order of truth. Responsible for all of them, I awaken a universal life. […][14] (pp. 86–87)
<<<>>> |
What Emerson remembers and retrieves here is what Merleau-Ponty described in his later years as the intercorporeality and reversibility—all the intertwining threads of intentionality—that have claimed him, in nature’s gift of embodiment, for the promise of a new ontology and new humanity. So, what Emerson is remembering is, first of all, his solidarity with the oppressed and the destitute—a question of ontological respect, sympathy, and responsibility.I remember the manifold cord—the thousand or the million stranded cord which my being and every man’s being is…, so that, if everyone should claim his part of me, I should be instantaneously diffused through creation and individually decease… I am alms for all and live but by the charity of others.
<<<>>> |
Convinced that “the perceiving mind is an incarnated mind”, Merleau-Ponty undertook to “restore the world of perception” and, in so doing, to “re-establish the roots of the mind in its body and in its world”. (POP 3). As in, for instance, re-establishing the roots of our vision in a sympathetic sensibility, such that, if we were to find ourselves witnessing terrible pain and suffering, that sight could readily induce the eyes to cry. (Of course, those roots, formed in our infancy, can be damaged, or we can become cut off from the roots, leaving us cold-hearted.)This subjectivity inherent in nature is not the result of a projection of a non-I outside of the [sovereign] I. We have to say, on the contrary, that what we call the I and what we call a living being have a common root in pre-objective being.[7] (p. 40. Italics added)
Thus, for instance, in the kind of dialog required by a flourishing democracy, “there would be constituted between the other person and myself a common ground”. My thought and that of the other could be “interwoven into a single fabric”. And in this way, we would, or rather could, become “collaborators” for each other “in consummate reciprocity”. Our perspectives could merge into each other; we would “co-exist through a common world”. (Ibid.)It is precisely my body which perceives the body of another person, and discovers in that other body a miraculous prolongation of my own intentions, a familiar way of dealing with the world. Henceforth, as the parts of my body together comprise a system, so my body and the other person’s body are one whole, two sides of one and the same phenomenon, and the anonymous existence of which my body is the ever-renewed trace henceforth inhabits both bodies simultaneously.(PP 354)
In this phenomenology, providing, as if in anticipation, the unifying primal corporeal dimension that Heidegger’s early phenomenology called for but missed until his texts of the late 1950s [23]5, the formation of the subject and object dualism is disclosed to be a later-constituted ontic structuring of our experience. (PP 430).We must rediscover, as anterior to the ideas of subject and object, the fact of my subjectivity and the nascent object, that primordial stage at which both things and ideas come into being.(PP 219. Italics added)
<<<>>> |
<<<>>> |
<<<>>> |
Today, with artificial intelligence creating cynical suspicion and doubts regarding the difference between fact and fiction, reality and fantasy, we desperately need the experience of intercorporeality and its reversibility, in order to recover a shared reality—and a shared sense of trust and moral responsibility. Retrieving something of this intercorporeality and our body’s felt sense of reversibility, perhaps we could learn the importance of reciprocity, a fundamental condition necessary for the institution of justice. Such, I think, is the intention behind the distinctively ontological inflection in Merleau-Ponty’s last revisioning of his phenomenological project.Just as the perception of a thing opens me up to being, by realizing the paradoxical synthesis of an infinity of perceptual aspects, in the same way the perception of the other founds morality by realizing the paradox of an alter ego, of a common situation, by placing my perspectives and my incommunicable solitude in the visual field of another and of all the others.(Ibid.)
<<<>>> |
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Hereafter designated by POP. The philosopher wrote these words in November, 1946. He thought of his phenomenology as singularly able to appreciate the ambiguities in the intertwinings and reversibilities operating in our experience. In this regard, Georges Simenon, the great Belgian author of the Inspector Maigret detective novels, once evoked Rembrandt, making a truly profound observation. In “When I Was Old”, he wrote: “His chiaroscuro is already a critique of pure reason”. This critique of reason could also describe the intention behind Merleau-Ponty’s attention to the evidence of ambiguity in his phenomenology of perception. This evidence is an unmistakable correction to Husserl’s claim of apodeictic evidence in transcendental phenomenology. |
2 | Hölderlin’s German is “Laß mich menschlich sprechen”. |
3 | A similar ethical and spiritual connectedness, likewise emergent from the openness of an ontology released from the dualisms self-other, subject-object, and mind-body, figures in Walt Whitman’s poems “Song of Myself” and “Salut au Monde” published in his collection Leaves of Grass. |
4 | Merleau-Ponty, SN 62. In “The Indirect Language”, Merleau-Ponty argues that, “In its blindness to the perceived world, analytic thought breaks the perceptual transition from one place to another and from one perspective to another and then looks to the mind for the guarantee of a unity that is already in perception. It also breaks the unity of culture and then tries to reconstitute it”. The Prose of the World, 82. Hereafter signified by PW. |
5 | After Heidegger left Being and Time, he grew increasingly unhappy with the way he had approached and handled the experience and understanding of being called for by the question of being. And so, by 1943, he would write, in “Aletheia (Heraclitus, Fragment B 16)” these crucial questions: “Why is it that we are ever and again so quick to forget the subjectivity that belongs to every objectivity? And how does it happen that even when we do note that they belong together, we still try to explain each from the standpoint of the other, or introduce some third element which is supposed to embrace subject and object?” And “Why is it”, he wonders, asking both himself and us a truly decisive question, “that we stubbornly resist considering even once whether the belonging together of subject and object [or, for that matter, the relation of Dasein and Sein] does not arise from something that first imparts their nature to both the object and its objectivity, and the subject and its subjectivity, and hence is prior to the realm of their reciprocity [ihres Wechselbezuges] as completely distinct [i.e., in their oppositionality, their Gegen-ständlichkeit]?” [33] (p. 103). Some years later, in “The Principle of Identity” (1957) and Time and Being (1962), he was finally able to answer his own questions, boldly calling our attention to the haunting presence of a dimension prior to and underlying the exclusionary structures of mind and body, subject and object, self and other. But his much earlier 1927 approach to the Seinsfrage, addressing it in Being and Time in terms of a conceptual paradigm that compels the understanding to represent Dasein and Sein in their enduring subject-object oppositionality, was in fact already troubling him, around the time when he was working on Being and Time. Thus, in Fundamental Problems of Phenomenology, a lecture course that he gave in 1927, Heidegger said: “We saw with reference to the perceivedness of the perceived [bezüglich der Wahrgenommenheit des Wahrgenommenen] that on the one hand it is a determination of the perceived entity but on the other hand it belongs to the perceiving—it is in a certain way objective and in a certain way subjective. But the complete separation of subject and object misses the [underlying] unity of the phenomenon. (Gesamtausgabe 24: 447; The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, 314). There are many parallels and affinities between Heidegger’s endeavor to overcome the dualisms and Merleau-Ponty’s, no doubt in part because of the influence of Heidegger on Merleau-Ponty’s thinking. This influence is most notable in Merleau-Ponty’s very last texts, in which “ontology” becomes one of his key deconstructive terms. In this regard, it is worth noting, for instance, that, in his late texts (“The Principle of Identity” and Time and Being), Heidegger introduced some new words to describe the phenomenology of reversibility: one of his words, “Gegenschwung”, meaning oscillation, can also be translated as “reversibility”. He also speaks of a certain “Schweben” in his efforts to deconstruct the dualisms imposed on our experience. With these terms, he really does get at the bodily felt nature of reversibility as actually experienced—even though he gives no explicit recognition to the intercorporeality that is involved. So, the major difference between the two philosophers comes down to the fact that Heidegger does not explicitly embody this reversibility in intercorporeality. He does, however, intend and appreciate the consequences for ethical life of this way of overcoming the dualisms still ravaging our existence—as his lifelong struggle against their authority confirms. |
6 | Perhaps this is an important part of what Ralph Waldo Emerson had in mind when he wrote that “Infancy is the perpetual Messiah which comes into the arms of fallen men, and pleads with them to return to paradise” [41] (p. 146). Or, if we cannot ever really “return to paradise”, let’s say instead that what is at stake in our retrieving something of the experience of infancy is at least the achievement, in our adult lifetime, of a more humane, more caring world. So, interpreting the messianic theology in more phenomenological terms, I take the essence of Emerson’s point to be that the nature of our infancy is the gift of a potential that awaits its recollection and actualization in our adult life. |
References
- Wittgenstein, L. Philosophical Investigations; Anscombe, G.E.M., Translator; The Macmillan Company: New York, NY, USA, 1953; p. 178e. [Google Scholar]
- Eliot, T.S. The Dry Salvages. In Collected Poems 1909–1962; Eliot, T.S., Ed.; Harcourt Brace & World: New York, NY, USA, 1963; p. 199. [Google Scholar]
- Stoljar, M.M., Translator; Novalis (Friedrich von Hardenberg). In Philosophical Writings; SUNY Press: Albany, NY, USA, 1997; “General Draft”; p. 128. [Google Scholar]
- Nietzsche. Thus Spoke Zarathustra; Kaufmann, W., Translator; Random House: New York, NY, USA, 1954; p. 70. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. GA 9: 352. In Pathmarks; McNeill, W., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1998; p. 268. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. The Primacy of Perception and Its Philosophical Consequences. In The Primacy of Perception; Edie, J.M., Translator; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1964; p. 13. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Nature: Course Notes from the Collège de France; Vallier, R., Translator; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 2003; p. 135. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. The Crisis of the Understanding. In The Primacy of Perception; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1964; p. 206. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Interrogation and Dialectic. In The Visible and the Invisible; Lingis, A., Translator; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1964; pp. 73–74, Hereafter designated by VI. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. The Metaphysical in Man. In Sense and Non-Sense; Dreyfus, P.A., Translator; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1992; p. 92, Hereafter designated by SN. [Google Scholar]
- Morris, D. Merleau-Ponty’s Developmental Ontology; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Hölderlin, F. Sämtliche Werke und Briefe; Knaupp, M., Ed.; Carl Hauser Verlag: München: Germany, 1992; Volume I, p. 513. [Google Scholar]
- Hölderlin, F. Sämtliche Werke; Tempel-Verlag: Berlin, Germany; Darmstadt, Germany, 1960; p. 584. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. The Prose of the World; O’Neill, J., Translator; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1963; Hereafter designated by PW. [Google Scholar]
- Emerson, R.W. The Early Lectures of Ralph Waldo Emerson 1833–1836; Whicher, S.E., Spiller, R.E., Eds.; Belnap Press, Harvard University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1959; Volume I, p. 69. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Science and the Experience of Expression; Gallimard: Paris, France, 1969. [Google Scholar]
- Beckett, S. The Unnameable; Grove Press: New York, NY, USA, 1970; p. 22. [Google Scholar]
- Eliot, T.S. Eyes that last I saw in tears. In Collected Poems 1909–1962; Harcourt Brace Jovanovich: New York, NY, USA, 1963; p. 133. [Google Scholar]
- Adorno, T.W. Resignation. In Critical Models: Interventions and Catchwords; Pickford, H.W., Translator; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1998; p. 293. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. The Philosopher and His Shadow. In Signs; McCleary, R.C., Ed.; NUP: Evanston, IL, USA, 1964; p. 167. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Phenomenology of Perception; Smith, C., Translator; Routledge & Kegan Paul: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1962; pp. 351–352. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. The Child’s Relations with Others. In The Primacy of Perception; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1964. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. The Visible and the Invisible; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1968. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Themes from the Lectures at the Collège de France 1952–1960; O’Neill, J., Translator; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1970. [Google Scholar]
- Davis, D. Reverse Subjectivity. In Merleau-Ponty Vivant; Dillon, M.C., Ed.; State University of New York Press: Albany, NY, USA, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Johnson, G.A. Introduction: Alterity as a Reversibility. In Ontology and Alterity in Merleau-Ponty; Johnson, G.A., Smith, M., Eds.; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1990; p. xxiv. [Google Scholar]
- Moran, D. Intercorporeality and Intersubjectivity: A Phenomenological Exploration of Embodiment; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Stawarska, B. From the Body Proper to the Flesh. In Feminist Interpretations of Maurice Merleau-Ponty; Olkowski, D., Weiss, G., Eds.; Penn State University: University Park, PA, USA, 2007; pp. 91–106. [Google Scholar]
- Olkowski, D. Only Nature is Mother to the Child. In Feminist Interpretations of Maurice Merleau-Ponty; Olkowski, D., Weiss, G., Eds.; Penn State University: University Park, PA, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Langer, M. Merleau-Ponty and Deep Ecology. In Ontology and Alterity in Merleau-Ponty; Johnson, G.A., Smith, M., Eds.; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Dillon, M.C. Merleau-Ponty Vivant; State University of New York: Albany, NY, USA, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Dillon, M.C. Merleau-Ponty’s Ontology; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, M. Early Greek Thinking; Krell, D.F.; Capuzzi, F.A., Translators; Harper & Row: New York, NY, USA, 1975. [Google Scholar]
- Kohlberg, L. The Philosophy of Moral Development; Harper & Row: New York, NY, USA, 1981. [Google Scholar]
- Kohlberg, L. Essays in Moral Development, Vol. 2, The Psychology of Moral Development; Harper and Row: San Francisco, CA, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, J. The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity; Lawrence, F., Translator; MIT: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1987. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, J. Moral Development and Ego Identity. In Communication and the Evolution of Society; Beacon Press: Boston, MA, USA, 1979. [Google Scholar]
- Williams, B. The Idea of Equality. In Philosophy, Politics and Society; Laslett, P., Runciman, W.G., Eds.; Basil Blackwell: Oxford, UK, 1962. [Google Scholar]
- Alighieri, D. Purgatorio, bilingual ed.; Merwin, W.S., Translator; Alfred A. Knopf: New York, NY, USA, 2000; pp. XVII, ll, 127–129, 168–169. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. The Concept of Nature. In Themes from the Lectures at the Collège de France 1952–1960; O’Neill, J., Translator; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1970; p. 82. [Google Scholar]
- Emerson, R.W. Nature. In Essays and Lectures; Porte, J., Ed.; The Library of America: New York, NY, USA, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Fisher, M. Capitalist Realism: Is There No Alternative? Zero Books: New York, NY, USA, 2022; p. 30. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Kleinberg-Levin, D.M. Intercorporeality, Moral Self-Development and Openness to Alterity: On Merleau-Ponty’s Redeeming of Childhood Experience. Philosophies 2024, 9, 156. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9050156
Kleinberg-Levin DM. Intercorporeality, Moral Self-Development and Openness to Alterity: On Merleau-Ponty’s Redeeming of Childhood Experience. Philosophies. 2024; 9(5):156. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9050156
Chicago/Turabian StyleKleinberg-Levin, David M. 2024. "Intercorporeality, Moral Self-Development and Openness to Alterity: On Merleau-Ponty’s Redeeming of Childhood Experience" Philosophies 9, no. 5: 156. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9050156
APA StyleKleinberg-Levin, D. M. (2024). Intercorporeality, Moral Self-Development and Openness to Alterity: On Merleau-Ponty’s Redeeming of Childhood Experience. Philosophies, 9(5), 156. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9050156