Toward a Logic of the Organism: A Process Philosophical Consideration
Abstract
:1. Introduction: On the Concept of the Organism
2. Phenomenal and Ontological Analysis of the Organism
2.1. Three Levels of Phenomenal Analysis of Organism
2.1.1. Organism as the Body of a Living Being
2.1.2. Emphasis on Metabolism as the Most Essential Feature of Organisms
2.1.3. Emphasis on the Autonomy of Organismic Self-Organization—The Need for the Formulation of a Logic of the Organism
- (i)
- There are many notable examples demonstrating the striking ontogenetic plasticity of multicellular organisms. The well-known theoretical biologist Mary Jane West-Eberhard is noted for arguing that phenotypic and developmental plasticity play a seminal role in animal evolution and speciation. In her influential book Developmental Plasticity and Evolution, she defines ‘plasticity’ or ‘phenotypic plasticity’ as “the ability of an organism to react to an environmental input with a change in form, state, movement or rate of activity” [17] (p. 34). This ability enables ontogenetic development to respond to challenges imposed by the conditions of life as well as to genetic challenges. West-Eberhard provides one of the most remarkable examples of animal plasticity: A goat, which was born without front legs, “adopted semi-upright posture and bipedal locomotion from the time of its birth” [17] (p. 51). When after a year of bipedal life the goat died due to an accident, it had developed behavioral specializations similar to those of kangaroos, and other bipedal mammals, such as “the ability to hop rapidly when disturbed” [17] (p. 51). The clinical autopsy revealed many morphological changes in its innervation, musculature, and skeleton, such as enlarged hind legs, a curved spine, an unusually large neck, a thorax similar to that found in kangaroos, and a wide sternum resembling that of an orangutan [17] (p. 52). According to evolutionary theorist and geneticist Eva Jablonka, those correlated phenotypic changes are due to flexible mechanical reorganization, new regulatory interactions, and “exploratory processes followed by stabilization at the cellular, physiological and behavioral level”, whereas at the molecular level, developmental plasticity “can involve epigenetic changes in regulatory systems” [16] (p. 101).
- (ii)
- Experiments with larvae of the fruit fly Drosophila melanogaster demonstrate the same radical plasticity of developing individuals that enables them to appropriately react “to a challenge that the species can never before have encountered” [16] (p. 102): In artificially created lines of flies a gene that resists a specific drug was linked to various tissue-specific promoters, so that it could only be expressed in some tissues but not in others. Then the fly larvae were fed with food contaminated with a toxic concentration of the drug. The flies would only then survive if the gene were expressed in additional tissues. Indeed, after a developmental delay, the promoter activity had been extended over other tissues, so that the resistance gene was expressed in the gut and other organs, thus enabling the larvae to tolerate the otherwise lethal dose [18].
- (iii)
- There are examples of organisms responding to different kinds of challenges through the reorganization of their material structure that cannot be subsumed under the technical term ‘plasticity’ because this term does not cover the entire spectrum of cases in which an organism transforms its structure. The highly influential French biophilosopher, epistemologist, and physician Georges Canguilhem describes an experiment providing evidence for what he refers to as the ‘vicariance of function’, meaning the ability of organs to serve multiple purposes: A placenta of a pregnant rabbit, that was extracted from the uterus and placed in the peritoneal cavity, grafted itself onto the intestine and nourished itself normally. When the graft was completed, the rabbit’s ovaries were operationally removed, which suppressed the function fulfilled by the corpus luteum during pregnancy. This resulted to the immediate abortion of all the placentas inside the uterus so that only the placenta that was grafted on the intestine survived and came to term. “Here is an example where the intestine behaves like a uterus, even, one could say, with more success than the uterus itself” [19] (p. 89).
- (iv)
- Fascinating examples of genetic and epigenetic reorganization are encountered when, due to interspecific or intraspecific hybridization, “two, often very different, genomes” are present “in the same nucleus” [16] (p. 104f.). This gives rise to serious problems, such as the disruption of the usual pattern of gene expression and the improper formation of chromosome pairs during meiosis. The hybrids, however, sometimes succeed in overcoming these difficulties through “widespread, extremely rapid, reproducible, targeted, genetic and epigenetic modifications” [16] (p. 105).
- (v)
- There is also striking evidence that both unicellular organisms and cells of multicellular organisms implement various modifications of their material structure which purposefully direct the course of intracellular molecular reactions [20] (pp. 2, 4), [21] (p. 35). In addition, as it will be shown in Section 3 of the present article, there is an impressive body of evidence that the shape modification of a cell plays a crucial role in governing metabolic and functional processes [22] (p. 5).
2.2. The Causal-Ontological Analysis of the Organism
2.2.1. The Substance-Ontological Approach
2.2.2. The System-Ontological Approach and the Logic of Systems Biological Mechanisms
- (i)
- In the mathematical mechanisms employed in the models of systems biology, the number of first-order extrinsic factors exceeds several times the number of the first-order intrinsic factors.
- (ii)
- The second-order factor of these mechanisms is always an extrinsic factor.
2.2.3. Process Ontological Approaches
3. The Logic of the Organism
3.1. The Second-Order Intrinsic Factor Is a Self
3.2. The Second-Order Intrinsic Factor Acts in an Umwelt
3.3. The Second-Order Intrinsic Factor Varies Its State Space
3.4. The Logic of the Organism Harmonizes Well with Process Ontology
4. On the New Project of Biological Statistical Mechanics: Heuristic Value Meets Ontological Openness
5. Conclusions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Toepfer, G. Organism. In Historical Dictionary of Biology. History and Theory of Fundamental Biological Concepts; Toepfer, G., Ed.; J. B. Metzler: Weimar, Germany, 2011; Volume 2, pp. 777–842. [Google Scholar]
- Koutroufinis, S.A. Organismus als Prozess. Begründung einer neuen Biophilosophie [Organism as Process. Foundations for a New Biophilosophy], 1st ed.; Karl Alber: Munich, Germany, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Koutroufinis, S.A. Beyond systems-theoretical Explanations of an Organism’s Becoming: A Process Philosophical Approach. In Life and Process. Towards a New Biophilosophy; Koutroufinis, S.A., Ed.; Walter de Gruyter: Berlin, Germany; Boston, MA, USA, 2014; pp. 99–132. [Google Scholar]
- Uexküll, J.V. Theoretical Biology, 1st ed.; Harcourt, Brace & Co.: New York, NY, USA; Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.: London, UK, 1926. [Google Scholar]
- Schark, M. The concept of organism, the concept of living being and the question of the naturalisability of the concept of function. In Organism. The Explanation of the Living; Toepfer, G., Michelini, F., Eds.; Karl Alber: Munich, Germany, 2016; pp. 213–235. [Google Scholar]
- Thompson, E. Mind in Life. Biology, Phenomenology, and the Science of Mind, 1st ed.; The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA; London, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Jonas, H. The Phenomenon of Life. Toward a Philosophical Biology; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Vane-Wright, R.I. What is Life? Biol. J. Linn. Soc. 2014, 112, 219–241. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Rosslenbroich, B. Properties of Life: Toward a Coherent Understanding of the Organism. Acta Biotheor. 2016, 64, 277–307. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pradeu, T. What is an Organism? An Immunological Answer. Hist. Phil. Life Sci. 2010, 32, 247–267. [Google Scholar]
- Schark, M. What are living beings? An Aristotelian approach. In Aristotle and Contemporary Biology. Comparative Studies; Heinemann, G., Timme, R., Eds.; Karl Alber: Munich, Germany, 2016; pp. 125–142. [Google Scholar]
- Jonas, H. Spinoza and the theory of organism. J. Hist. Philos. 1965, 3, 43–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shapiro, J.A. Evolution: A View from the 21st Century, 1st ed.; FT Press Science: Upper Saddle River, NJ, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Sultan, S.E. Organism & Environment. Ecological Development, Niche Construction, and Adaptation; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Jablonka, E. The evolutionary implications of epigenetic inheritance. Interface Focus 2017, 7, 20160135. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Jablonka, E. Epigenetic inheritance and plasticity: The responsive germline. Prog. Biophys. Mol. 2013, 111, 99–107. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- West-Eberhard, M.J. Developmental Plasticity and Evolution; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Stern, S.; Fridmann-Sirkis, Y.; Braun, E.; Soen, Y. Epigenetically heritable alteration of fly development in response to toxic challenge. Cell. Rep. 2012, 1, 528–542. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Canguilhem, G. Knowledge of Life; Fordham University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Giuliani, A. Collective motions and specific effectors: A statistical mechanics perspective on biological regulation. BMC Genom. 2010, 11 (Suppl. 1), 1–13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Bizzarri, M.; Palombo, A.; Cucina, A. Theoretical aspects of Systems Biology. Prog. Biophys. Mol. 2013, 112, 33–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Bizzarri, M.; Naimark, O.; Nieto-Villar, J.; Fedeli, V.; Giuliani, A. Complexity in Biological Organization: Deconstruction (and Subsequent Restating) of Key Concepts. Entropy 2020, 22, 885. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Koutroufinis, S.A. Organism, Process, Machine. Towards a Process Ontology for Organismic Dynamics. Organisms. J. Biol. Sci. 2017, 1, 23–44. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. Metaphysics; Hackett Publishing Company: Indianapolis, IN, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. Physics; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. De Anima; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1968. [Google Scholar]
- Koutroufinis, S.A. Modern Biological Neo-Teleologism vs. Aristotle’s Genuine Telos. Biocosmology–Neo-Aristotelism 2016, 6, 414–426. [Google Scholar]
- Bertalanffy, L.V. General System Theory; Allen Lane The Penguin Press: London, UK, 1971. [Google Scholar]
- Descartes, R. Description du corps humaine. In Ouvres de Descartes (Vol. XI); Adam, C., Tannery, P., Eds.; Vrin: Paris, France, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Rothschuh, K. Physiologie. Der Wandel ihrer Konzepte, Probleme und Methoden vom 16. bis 19. Jahrhundert [Physiology. The Change of Their Concepts, Problems and Methods from the 16th to the 19th Century]; Karl Alber: Munich, Germany, 1968. [Google Scholar]
- Bertalanffy, L.V. An Outline of General System Theory. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 1950, 1, 114–129. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Goodwin, B. How the Leopard Changed Its Spots; Phoenix: London, UK, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Kauffman, S. The Origins of Order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Kauffman, S. At Home in the Universe: The Search for Laws of Self-Organization and Complexity; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Waddington, C.H. (Ed.) Towards a Theoretical Biology (Vol. I–IV); Edinburgh University Press: Edinburgh, UK, 1968–1972. [Google Scholar]
- Ebeling, W.; Sokolov, I. Statistical Thermodynamics and Stochastic Theory of Nonequilibrium Systems; World Scientific Publishing: Hackensack, NJ, USA; London, UK; Singapore, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- MacLeod, M.; Nersessian, N. Building Simulations from the Ground Up: Modelling and Theory in Systems Biology. Philos. Sci. 2013, 80, 533–556. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Bechtel, W.; Abrahamsen, A. Dynamic mechanistic explanation. Computational modeling of circadian rhythms as an exemplar for cognitive science. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 2010, 41, 321–333. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Bechtel, W.; Abrahamson, A. Explanation: A Mechanist Alternative. Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. Biomed. Sci. 2005, 36, 421–441. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Glennan, S. Mechanisms and the Nature of Causation. Erkenntnis 1996, 44, 49–71. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Glennan, S.; Illari, P. Varieties of Mechanisms. In The Routledge Handbook of Mechanisms and Mechanical Philosophy; Glennan, S., Illari, P., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2018; pp. 91–103. [Google Scholar]
- Machamer, P.; Darden, L.; Craver, C.F. Thinking about Mechanisms. Philos. Sci. 2000, 67, 1–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Brigandt, I. Explanation of Molecular Processes without Tracking Mechanism Operation. Philos. Sci. 2018, 85, 984–997. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Brigandt, I.; Green, S.; O’Malley, M.A. Systems biology and mechanistic explanation. In The Routledge Handbook of Mechanisms and Mechanical Philosophy; Glennan, S., Illari, P., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2018; pp. 362–374. [Google Scholar]
- Karr, J.; Sanghvi, J.; Macklin, D.N.; Gutschow, M.V.; Jacobs, J.M.; Bolival, B., Jr.; Assad-Garcia, N.; Glass, J.I.; Covert, M.W. A Whole-Cell Computational Model Predicts Phenotype from Genotype. Cell 2012, 150, 389–401. Available online: http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0092867412007763 (accessed on 20 November 2021). [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Murray, J.D. Mathematical Biology; Springer: New York, NY, USA; Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Meinhardt, H.; Gierer, A. Pattern formation by local self-activation and lateral inhibition. BioEssays 2000, 22, 753–760. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Hoek, M.J. Evolutionary Dynamics of Metabolic Adaptation. Ph.D. Thesis, Utrecht University of Utrecht, Utrecht, The Netherlands, 5 March 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Tyson, J.J.; Chen, K.C.; Novak, B. Sniffer, Buzzers, Toogles and Blinkers: Dynamics of Regulatory and Signaling Pathways in the Cell. Curr. Opin. Cell Biol. 2003, 15, 221–231. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Downward, J. The ins and outs of signaling. Nature 2001, 411, 759–762. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Ferrel, J.E., Jr.; Xiong, W. Bistability in Cell Signaling: How to Make Continuous Processes Discontinuous, and Reversible Processes Irreversible. Chaos 2001, 11, 227–236. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gardner, T.S.; Cantor, C.R.; Collins, J.J. Construction of a genetic toggle switch in Escherichia coli. Nature 2000, 403, 339–342. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Elowitz, M.B.; Leibler, S. A synthetic oscillatory network of transcriptional regulators. Nature 2000, 403, 335–338. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Panning, T.D.; Watson, L.T.; Tyson, J.J.; Shaffer, C.A. A Mathematical Programming Formulation for the Budding Yeast Cell Cycle. Simulation 2007, 83, 497–514. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Gorban, A.N.; Tyukina, T.A.; Pokidysheva, L.I.; Smirnova, E.V. Dynamic and thermodynamic models of adaptation. Phys. Life Rev. 2021, 37, 17–64. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Voit, E.O. Computational Analysis of Biochemical Systems; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Breidenmoser, T.; Wolkenhauer, O. Explanation and Organizing Principles in Systems Biology. In Explanation in Biology. An Inquiry into Diversity of Explanatory Patterns in the Life Sciences; Braillard, P.A., Malaterre, C., Eds.; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherland; Heidelberg, Germany; New York, NY, USA, 2015; pp. 249–264. [Google Scholar]
- Zwolak, J.W.; Tyson, J.J.; Watson, L.T. Parameter Estimation for a Mathematical Model of the Cell Cycle in Frog Eggs. J. Comput. Biol. 2005, 12, 48–63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Transtrum, M.K.; Machta, B.B.; Brown, K.S.; Daniels, B.C.; Myers, C.R.; Sethna, J.P. Perspective: Sloppiness and emergent theories in physics, biology, and beyond. J. Chem. Phys. 2015, 143, 010901. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Craver, C.F. Functions and mechanisms: A perspectivalist view. In Functions: Selection and Mechanisms; Huneman, P., Ed.; Springer: Berlin, Germany, 2013; pp. 133–158. [Google Scholar]
- Kaplan, D.M. Mechanisms and Dynamical Systems. In The Routledge Handbook of Mechanisms and Mechanical Philosophy; Glennan, S., Illari, P., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2018; pp. 267–280. [Google Scholar]
- Nicholson, D.J. The concept of mechanism in biology. Stud. Hist. Philos. Biol. Biomed. Sci. 2012, 43, 152–163. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Wolpert, L. Development: Is the egg computable or could we generate an angel or a dinosaur? In What is Life? The Next Fifty Years: Speculations on the Future of Biology; Murphy, M.P., O’Neill, L.A.J., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1995; pp. 57–66. [Google Scholar]
- Koene, R.A. Uploading to Substrate-Independent Minds. In The Transhumanist Reader. Classical and Contemporary Essays on the Science, Technology, and Philosophy of the Human Future; More, M., Vita-More, N., Eds.; Wiley-Blackwell: West Sussex, UK, 2013; pp. 146–156. [Google Scholar]
- Dupré, J.; Nicholson, D.J. A Manifesto for a Processual Philosophy of Biology. In Everything Flows. Towards a Processual Philosophy of Biology; Nicholson, D.J., Dupré, J., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2018; pp. 3–45. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehead, A.N. Process and Reality. An Essay in Cosmology; Free Press: New York, NY, USA, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Woodger, J.H. Biological Principles. A Critical Study; Harcourt, Brace & Co.: New York, NY, USA; Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.: London, UK, 1929. [Google Scholar]
- Agar, W.E. A Contribution to the Theory of the Living Organism; Melbourne University Press: Melbourne, Australia; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1943. [Google Scholar]
- Lillie, R.S. General Biology and Philosophy of Organism; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1945. [Google Scholar]
- Waddington, C.H. Die Biologischen Grundlagen des Lebens [The Biological Foundations of Life]; Friedrich Vieweg & Sohn: Braunschweig, Germany, 1966. [Google Scholar]
- Waddington, C.H. Whitehead and Modern Science. In Mind in Nature. Essays on the Interface of Science and Philosophy; Cobb, J.B., Jr., Griffin, D.R., Eds.; University Press of America: Washington, DC, USA, 1977; pp. 143–146. [Google Scholar]
- Laszlo, E. Introduction to Systems Philosophy. Toward a New Paradigm of Contemporary Thought; Gordon and Breach, Science Publishers: New York, NY, USA; London, UK; Paris, France, 1972. [Google Scholar]
- Birch, C. Can Evolution be Accounted for Solely in terms of Mechanical Causation? In Mind in Nature. Essays on the Interface of Science and Philosophy; Cobb, J.B., Jr., Griffin, D.R., Eds.; University Press of America: Washington, DC, USA, 1977; pp. 13–18. [Google Scholar]
- Birch, C.L. Whitehead and science education. Educ. Philos. Theory 1988, 20, 33–41. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Birch, C.L.; Cobb, J.B., Jr. The Liberation of Life. From the Cell to the Community; Environmental Ethics Books: Denton, TX, USA, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Hameroff, S. How quantum brain biology can rescue conscious free will. Front. Integr. Neurosci. 2012, 6, 93. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Hameroff, S.; Penrose, R. Conscious Events as Orchestrated Space-Time Selections. J. Conscious. Stud. 1996, 3, 36–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stapp, H. The Effect of Mind upon Brain. In Life and Process. Towards a New Biophilosophy; Koutroufinis, S.A., Ed.; Walter de Gruyter: Berlin, Germany; Boston, MA, USA, 2014; pp. 183–213. [Google Scholar]
- Falkner, G.G.; Falkner, R.A. Die Entwicklung der Lebewesen in Erfahrungsakten [The Development of Living Beings in Acts of Experience]; Karl Alber: Munich, Germany, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Hartshorne, C. Born to Sing. An Interpretation and World Survey of Bird Song; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 1973. [Google Scholar]
- Cobb, J.B., Jr. A Fourth Variable in Evolution. In Life and Process. Towards a New Biophilosophy; Koutroufinis, S.A., Ed.; Walter de Gruyter: Berlin, Germany; Boston, MA, USA, 2014; pp. 215–224. [Google Scholar]
- Griffin, D.R. Of Minds and Molecules. In The Reenchantment of Science; Griffin, D.R., Ed.; State University of New York Press: New York, NY, USA, 1988; pp. 141–163. [Google Scholar]
- Griffin, D.R. Evolution without Tears. In Life and Process. Towards a New Biophilosophy; Koutroufinis, S.A., Ed.; Walter de Gruyter: Berlin, Germany; Boston, MA, USA, 2014; pp. 255–273. [Google Scholar]
- Deacon, T.W.; Koutroufinis, S.A. Complexity and Dynamical Depth. Information 2014, 5, 404–423. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Deacon, T.W. Incomplete Nature. How Mind Emerged from Matter; Norton & Co.: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Nicholson, D.J. Reconceptualizing the Organism. From Complex Machine to Flowing Stream. In Everything Flows. Towards a Processual Philosophy of Biology; Nicholson, D.J., Dupré, J., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Uexküll, J.V. Umwelt und Innenwelt der Tiere [Umwelt and Inner World of Animals]; Springer: Berlin, Germany, 1909. [Google Scholar]
- Koutroufinis, S.A. Organism, self, Umwelt: An anti-mechanistic approach to organismic individuality. Thaumàzein 2020, 8, 260–274. [Google Scholar]
- Falkner, G.G.; Falkner, R.A. The Experience of Environmental Phosphate Fluctuations by Cyanobacteria. In Life and Process. Towards a New Biophilosophy; Koutroufinis, S.A., Ed.; Walter de Gruyter: Berlin, Germany; Boston, MA, USA, 2014; pp. 73–97. [Google Scholar]
- Montévil, M. Historicity at the heart of biology. Theory Biosci. 2020, 1–9. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Kauffman, S. What is Life? In The Next Fifty Years: Science in the First Half of the Twenty-First Century; Brockman, J., Ed.; Vintage Books: New York, NY, USA, 2002; pp. 126–141. [Google Scholar]
- Longo, G.; Montévil, M. Perspectives on Organisms. Biological Time, Symmetries and Singularities; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2014. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2021 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Koutroufinis, S.A. Toward a Logic of the Organism: A Process Philosophical Consideration. Entropy 2022, 24, 66. https://doi.org/10.3390/e24010066
Koutroufinis SA. Toward a Logic of the Organism: A Process Philosophical Consideration. Entropy. 2022; 24(1):66. https://doi.org/10.3390/e24010066
Chicago/Turabian StyleKoutroufinis, Spyridon A. 2022. "Toward a Logic of the Organism: A Process Philosophical Consideration" Entropy 24, no. 1: 66. https://doi.org/10.3390/e24010066
APA StyleKoutroufinis, S. A. (2022). Toward a Logic of the Organism: A Process Philosophical Consideration. Entropy, 24(1), 66. https://doi.org/10.3390/e24010066